A brief History of Time: From Big Bang to Black Holes
Download 2.18 Mb. Pdf ko'rish
|
The information paradox
One reason for my excitement over LIGO’s gravitational wave detections is that the area theorem is directly linked to a major controversy surrounding black holes known as the information paradox. Information is a sacred thing in physics; if we are able to describe the entire state of the universe today with a certain amount of information (the positions and speeds of all the particles, for example), we expect to need the same amount of information to describe the entire state of the universe tomorrow. This assumption underlies our ability to make scientific predictions, and is quietly built into Newton’s and Einstein’s work; it’s even part of quantum mechanics. One might therefore hope it will remain true when we formulate a final theory of quantum gravity. When a black hole is formed, information about individual objects that have fallen in (their shapes, sizes, and chemical compositions, for example) becomes obscured. The only information about what formed it, is its total mass, its spin and its possible electric charge. This is the so-called ‘no-hair’ theorem.This is not too much of a problem, since the objects can just be regarded as hidden away rather than entirely lost. But if, as I showed in a letter published in Nature in 1974, quantum mechanics allows black holes to lose their mass and disappear (p.119), there is a difficulty. After the black hole is gone, what has then happened to the information? When I wrote A Brief History of Time, I believed that the information concerning what had fallen into the black hole was truly lost, perhaps residing in a separate universe hived off from our own. In 1997 I even bet Caltech physics professor John Preskill an encyclopedia of his choice that I was right. It was only later, in 2004, that I realized I had been wrong, after considering what happens to black holes after an infinite amount of time has passed. The amount of information at the start and the end was the same! When I conceded, John asked for an encyclopedia of baseball which I duly gave him. (My attempt to persuade him that cricket is more interesting was unsuccessful.) My change of opinion started by considering one of the most remarkable discoveries to arise from string theory: there appears to be an exact correspondence between the behavior of gravity and an obscure branch of physics known as conformal field theory. The details of the link don’t matter for our purposes. All one needs to know is that anything described by conformal field theory – now including black holes – demonstrably preserves information. Very recently, it was realized that the ‘no-hair’ theorem was formulated in a way that was too restrictive. There is also supertranslation and superrotation hair. It seems that the information about material that formed the black hole remains preserved on the horizon as supertranslation and superrotation hair. We do not yet know if this is enough information to save the principles of quantum mechanics. Neither do we yet know how the information might emerge from the black hole. Even harder questions can be asked then about the fundamental nature of the singularities of spacetime that general relativity predicts must exist inside black holes. Of course, this abstract argument doesn’t tell us exactly how the lost information manages to leak back out of a black hole in practice. One must be clear that, when the information finally makes its way out of the black-hole-like region, it will emerge in a very hard-to-interpret format. It is like burning a book. Information is not technically lost, if one keeps the ashes and the smoke – which makes me think again about the baseball encyclopedia I gave John Preskill. I should perhaps have given him its burnt remains instead. Outlook In the twenty years since the last revision of this book, progress in cosmology has been rapid. Some of the developments, such as the detection of gravitational waves and the steady improvement in our understanding of the early universe, were anticipated; others, like dark energy and the accelerating universe, less so. Perhaps the most striking trend is one that many find uncomfortable: the no boundary proposal and eternal inflation point increasingly strongly to the idea that our universe is just one of many. Copernicus first suggested in the sixteenth century that we are not placed at the center of even our own universe (p. 4); yet we are still struggling to accept just how vanishingly small a fragment of reality our familiar world represents. It may not be much longer before the evidence for a multiverse becomes overwhelming. Despite the vastness of the multiverse, there is a sense in which we remain significant: we can still be proud to be part of a species that is working all this out. With that in mind, the coming years should be just as exciting as the last twenty. |
Ma'lumotlar bazasi mualliflik huquqi bilan himoyalangan ©fayllar.org 2024
ma'muriyatiga murojaat qiling
ma'muriyatiga murojaat qiling