Laclau and Mouffe: The Radical Democratic Imaginary
Structural positions, subject positions, identity and
Download 0.72 Mb. Pdf ko'rish
|
The-Radical-Democratic-Imaginary-oleh-Laclau-and-Mouffe
Structural positions, subject positions, identity and
antagonism From Laclau and Mouffe’s perspective, a fully constructivist theory of identity formation must go much further than those Marxist theories that merely recognize that political discourse can affect the formation of interests or that it can play a F R O M L E N I N T O G R A M S C I 56 secondary role in the reproduction of social structures. For the authors, discourse is prior to identity formation in the sense that identity is wholly constructed through discourse. Their embrace of constructivist theory has been widely criticized. Hall argues, for example, that his position differs from that of Laclau and Mouffe insofar as he does not believe that “just anything can be articulated with anything else.” He asserts that every discourse has specific “‘conditions of existence’ which, although they cannot fix or guarantee particular outcomes, set limits or constraints on the process of articulation itself.” Hall insists that although historical formations are contingent, they can be “deeply resistant to change” (Hall 1988a:10). Laclau and Mouffe would, however, agree that in the context of a particularly entrenched hegemonic project, the possibilities for subversive interventions and re-articulations in a given social formation would in fact be limited. They do not hold that politics has become a game in which everything is equally possible and every position has equal value. They speak extensively about the ways in which political strategies must always be deployed in specific contexts and recognize that relations of domination may prevail in those contexts (Laclau and Mouffe 1985:149–94). Laclau also situates his more recent arguments about subjectivity within broader considerations about the processes of sedimentation, normalization and institutionalization (Laclau 1990a). By way of a response to Hall’s criticisms, and in the interest of clarifying Laclau and Mouffe’s theory, a distinction that is already implicit in their work will be brought to the fore, namely the distinction between structural positions and subject positions. Like all radical theories, radical democratic pluralist theory rejects the neo- conservative assumption that individuals freely choose their identity and freely utilize socio-economic networks and institutions to shape their material conditions according to their preferences. In the case of class, for example, radical democratic pluralist theory recognizes that in capitalist formations, those individuals who do not own the means of production must become workers; they must sell their labor according to conditions that are not of their choosing in order to survive. We could say, then, that an individual is structurally positioned within hierarchical social, cultural, political and economic systems by forces and institutions that are prior to her will. 2 Further, these structural positions shape the individual’s life chances, for they situate her within the relatively stable networks of power relations that shape the distribution of material resources. The masses of the poor and the homeless in the United States are not impoverished because of their low motivation, faulty self-esteem or inferior intelligence; their condition should be explained instead in terms of historical patterns of exploitation and oppression. The same holds true with respect to race and sex. In a racist and sexist society, no one chooses to be positioned as white, black, Latino/a, Asian, mixed race, male, female and so on; one finds oneself “always already” positioned by forces and institutions within a discursive field that is never wholly of our choosing. (I will critique the biological determinist conception of race and sex in Chapter 5.) F R O M L E N I N T O G R A M S C I 57 Following Gramsci, we could argue further that no one experiences her structural positions within the social in a direct and unmediated way. It is only through political discourses that we experience the ways in which we are positioned within social structures. In the metaphorical terms provided by psychoanalysis, we could say that discourse provides the imaginary framework through which we interpret the symbolic order into which we are thrown (Bellamy 1993:28). This process is contingent: there is no guarantee that one specific discourse will defeat all its rivals and become a predominant interpretative framework. The struggles between discourses to become predominant interpretative frameworks do tend to reflect the configuration of power relations in a given historical moment, but they are so complex that we cannot predict their exact outcomes. Some discourses may, given the strategic terrain, be more likely to become compelling frameworks, but none of them—not even the ones that seem to “reflect” predominant social structures— are utterly guaranteed to succeed. In any event, no individual can choose to stand outside the totality of interpretative frameworks; our fundamental dependence upon the interpretative function of discourse is written into our very human condition. Laclau argues, for example, that an individual’s class structural position becomes coherent for her through some specific and compelling political discourse (Laclau 1990a:9, 16). We could imagine the way that this might work for different workers on the same assembly line in an American factory. One worker might be influenced by neo-conservatism. She might believe that her position as a worker results from the fact that she made a greater effort in life than her neighbors on welfare. She might think that the corporate executives and the corporate shareholders owe their positions to luck, hard work, corruption, nepotism or maybe a combination of these and other factors. The second worker might be influenced by right-wing religious fundamentalism. She might claim that her neighbors on welfare are living lives of sinful sloth and sexual immorality, and that her own industriousness is a reflection of her Christian way of life. She might even believe that the executives’ and shareholders’ relatively better fortune is in part the result of God’s will. The third worker might be influenced by leftist leaders and the progressive wing of her trade union. She might believe that her position as a propertyless worker results from systematic exploitation, that she has in this sense much in common with her neighbor on welfare, and that the executives and shareholders won their positions thanks to the better opportunities that were systematically provided for them from birth onwards in a basically inegalitarian social order. These imaginary examples are already too abstract, for the interpretative frameworks described here do not have racial, gender, national and other elements blended fully into them whereas actual interpretative frameworks are always irreducibly multiple, complex and even contradictory. Political subjects may think one thing, state another, and act in yet another manner altogether. Perhaps their basic principles are reinterpreted in unpredictable ways whenever they are applied in specific circumstances; or perhaps their conscious affiliations are haunted by unconscious fixations and aversions. With these reservations in mind, we can F R O M L E N I N T O G R A M S C I 58 nevertheless assert that an individual’s sense of her structural positions—the way that she lives in her structural positions and responds to them—is shaped not by the mere fact of the structural positions themselves, but by the subject positions through which she lives her structural positions. 3 Furthermore, the meaning of each subject position is constituted with respect to its differential relations with the entire system of subject positions. I will return to the relational character of subject position formation below and in Chapter 3. This argument sets Laclau and Mouffe’s constructivism entirely apart from essentialist identity theory. An essentialist approach ignores the constitutive role of mediating political discourse, and assigns to the individual an “authentic” interest that is supposed to flow directly from her structural position. Hence propertyless workers are supposed to have an “authentic” interest in the socialist struggle to overthrow capitalism, just as women in sexist societies are supposed to have an “authentic” interest in the feminist struggle, and so on. Where individuals do not actually act in accordance with their putative “authentic” interest—where workers vote for conservatives, women reject feminism, racial minorities oppose affirmative action, and so on—the essentialist diagnosis is that they are caught in the grips of false consciousness and require firm leadership to guide them towards their “authentic” interests. The essentialist approach does not pay sufficient attention to the specificity of these individuals’ interpretative frameworks. There may be some very good reasons why a woman finds a particular anti-feminist interpretation more compelling than a feminist one in a given moment, and these reasons should be taken into account during the reconstruction of a more effective feminism. Laclau and Mouffe do not pursue the question of identity formation with the aim of piercing ideological distortions to arrive at the authentic subject. False consciousness theory assumes that we can stand in an objective position outside political discourse in order to establish the distinction between objective interests and ideological illusion. For Laclau, not only is it impossible for us to occupy such a position, this promise is itself an ideological illusion (1996i). Laclau and Mouffe define “subject positions” as “points of antagonism” and “forms of struggle” (1985:11). We will see in Chapter 3 that each subject position is constituted through its differential relations with other subject positions, in the form of equivalential and antagonistic relations at a given moment in time, and in the form of the “iterated” traces of genealogical precedents. At this point, however, we need to explore what a subject position does. Adding another element to Laclau and Mouffe’s theory, we could say that a “subject position” is like an “identity” in the following sense. A “subject position” refers to the ensemble of beliefs through which an individual interprets and responds to her structural positions within a social formation. In this sense, an individual only becomes a social agent insofar as she lives her structural positions through an ensemble of subject positions that makes sense to at least one other person in one other time and place. 4 F R O M L E N I N T O G R A M S C I 59 The relationship between subject positions and structural positions is often quite complex. Consider, for example, a white heterosexual bourgeois woman, living in a social formation characterized by highly stabilized structural hierarchies and yet a relative openness with respect to the availability of different interpretative frameworks. Her racialized, gendered, sexual and class structural positions are in this case largely determined by the social formations into which she is “thrown,” and it is largely her structural positions, rather than her free will, that shape her life chances. At the same time, her subject positions, the ways in which she lives her structural positions, will tend to be somewhat more vulnerable to political intervention and even the accidents of personal circumstance. That same individual could live her structural positions through subject positions such as liberal anti- racist Catholicism; socialist environmentalism or neo-conservative anti-feminism. In a social formation with stabilized structural hierarchies and a relatively closed set of normalized interpretative frameworks, however, a singular and rigidly defined set of subject positions will tend to operate as the only coherent interpretative frameworks through which structural positions are lived. This is often the case, for example, in religious fundamentalist communities or in strong nationalist movements. Strictly speaking, we cannot speak of a “false” subject position in the same way that some Marxists refer to “false” consciousness. Laclau asserts, for example, that workers take on radicalized identities solely because of the intervening effects of political discourses that come from outside the relations of production as such (Laclau 1990a:9, 16). Their identities do not emerge as a direct result of what I am calling their structural positions. We can refer to our working definitions of political values and suggest that in a given set of circumstances some subject positions will tend to have more democratic effects than others; radical democratic pluralist activists make these sorts of practical assessments all the time. The identity of the leftist worker in our imaginary factory, for example, expresses principles that are clearly quite close to radical democratic pluralism, while the principles expressed in the identities of the neo-conservative and the religious fundamentalist clearly oppose this project. The term “class” becomes problematic wherever it is used indiscriminately to refer to both of these facets of subjectivity, structural positions and subject positions. One is more or less assigned a class structural position within stable capitalist structures; as we saw in Chapter 1, there is very little class mobility in capitalist societies. All of our three workers—the neo-conservative, the religious fundamentalist and the leftist trade union supporter—are being exploited through their wage labor contracts, and, because their life chances are profoundly shaped by their working-class structural position, it is very unlikely that they will ever escape this condition. But we must recall that when we group individuals together by virtue of their shared structural position alone, we are actually referring to theoretical categories, and not to actual social agents who perform concrete social practices. In Marxist theory, for example, we use economic categories to depict the capitalist relations of production—the bourgeoisie/proletariat relation—and F R O M L E N I N T O G R A M S C I 60 actual social actors only appear in this model insofar as they are the “bearers” Download 0.72 Mb. Do'stlaringiz bilan baham: |
Ma'lumotlar bazasi mualliflik huquqi bilan himoyalangan ©fayllar.org 2024
ma'muriyatiga murojaat qiling
ma'muriyatiga murojaat qiling