RT3340X half title 6/22/06 11: 41 am page 1 The Disability


Download 5.02 Mb.
Pdf ko'rish
bet18/61
Sana05.10.2017
Hajmi5.02 Mb.
#17160
1   ...   14   15   16   17   18   19   20   21   ...   61


strict enforcement of the law forbidding abortion except for eugenic reasons (Koonz, 1987).

Th

  e next stage in the campaign of “selection and eradication” was opened at the Nazi party congress 



in 1935, where plans were made for the “destruction of lives not worth living.” Th

  e phrase was borrowed 

from the title of a book published much earlier, in 1920, by Alfred Hoche, professor of psychiatry 

and director of the Psychiatric Clinic at Freiburg, and Rudolf Binding, professor of jurisprudence at 

the University of Leipzig. In their book, entitled Th

  e Release for Destruction of Lives Not Worth Living 

(Die Freigabe zur Vernichtung lebensunwerten Lebens), these professors argued for killing “worthless” 

people, whom they defi ned as those who are “mentally completely dead” and those who constitute 

“a foreign body in human society” (quoted in Chorover, 1979, p. 97). At the time the program was 

initiated, the arguments focused on the money wasted in keeping institutionalized (hence “worth-

less”) people alive, for in the early stages the rationale of the euthanasia campaign was economic as 

much as eugenic. Th

  erefore the extermination campaign was directed primarily at inmates of state 

psychiatric hospitals and children living in state institutions for the mentally and physically disabled. 

Jews were specifi cally excluded because they were not considered worthy of euthanasia. (Here, too, 

the Nazis were not alone. In 1942, as the last inmates of German mental hospitals were being fi nished 

off , Dr. Foster Kennedy, an American psychiatrist writing in the offi

  cial publication of the American 

RT3340X_C007.indd   97

RT3340X_C007.indd   97

7/11/2006   9:46:42 AM

7/11/2006   9:46:42 AM



Ruth Hubbard

98

Psychiatric Association, advocated killing mentally retarded children of fi ve and older (Proctor, 1988). 



Th

  e arguments were phrased in humane terms like these: “Parents who have seen the diffi

  cult life of a 

crippled or feebleminded child must be convinced that though they have the moral obligation to care 

for the unfortunate creatures, the wider public should not be obliged . . . to assume the enormous costs 

that long-term institutionalization might entail” (quoted in Proctor, 1988, p. 183). Th

  is argument calls 

to mind the statement by Bentley Glass (1971) about parents not having “a right to burden society 

with a malformed or a mentally incompetent child.”

In Germany, the propaganda was subtle and widespread. For example, Proctor (1988, p. 184) cites 

practice problems in a high school mathematics text published for the school year 1935–36, in which 

students were asked to calculate the costs to the Reich of maintaining mentally ill people in various 

kinds of institutions for diff erent lengths of time and to compare the costs of constructing insane 

asylums and housing units. How is that for relevance?

Although the euthanasia program was planned in the mid-1930s, it was not implemented until 

1939, when wartime dislocation and secrecy made it relatively easy to institute such extreme measures. 

Two weeks before the invasion of Poland an advisory committee commissioned by Hitler issued a 

secret report recommending that children born with Down syndrome, microcephaly, and various 

deformities be registered with the Ministry of the Interior. Euthanasia, like sterilization, was to pro-

ceed with the trappings of selection. Th

  erefore physicians were asked to fi ll out questionnaires about 

all children in their care up to age three who had any of these kinds of disabilities. Th

 e completed 

questionnaires were sent to three-man committees of medical experts charged with marking each 

form “plus” or “minus.” Although none of these “experts” ever saw the children, those whose forms 

were marked “plus” were transferred to one of a number of institutions where they were killed. Some 

of the oldest and most respected hospitals in Germany served as such extermination centers. By 1941 

the program was expanded to include older children with disabilities and by 1943, to include healthy 

Jewish children. Also in 1939, evaluation forms were sent to psychiatric institutions for adults for 

selection and so-called euthanasia.

By September 1941 over seventy thousand inmates had been killed at some of the most distinguished 

psychiatric hospitals in Germany, which had been equipped for this purpose with gas chambers, 

disguised as showers, and with crematoria (Lift on, 1986; Proctor, 1988). (When the mass extermina-

tion of Jews and other “undesirables” began shortly thereaft er, these gas chambers were shipped east 

and installed at Auschwitz and other extermination camps.) Most patients were gassed or killed by 

injection with legal drugs, but a few physicians were reluctant to intervene so actively and let children 

die of slow starvation and the infectious diseases to which they became susceptible, referring to this 

as death from “natural” causes. Relatives were notifi ed that their family member had died suddenly 

of one of a number of infectious diseases and that the body had been cremated for reasons of public 

health. Nevertheless, rumors began to circulate, and by 1941 hospital killings virtually ceased because 

of protests, especially from the Church.

Th

  ere is a direct link between this campaign of “selection and eradication” and the subsequent 



genocide of Jews, gypsies, communists, homosexuals, and other “undesirables.” Early on these people 

were described as “diseased” and their presence, as an infection or a cancer in the body of the Volk. 

Proctor (1988, p. 194) calls this rationalization “the medicalization of antisemitism.” Th

 e point is 

that the Nazi leaders shouted anti-Semitic and racist propaganda from their platforms, but when it 

came to devising the measures for ridding the Th

  ousand Year Reich of Jews, gypsies, and the other 

undesirables, the task was shouldered by the scientists and physicians who had earlier devised the 

sterilization and euthanasia programs for the mentally or physically disabled. Th

 erefore, nothing came 

easier than a medical metaphor: Jews as cancer, Jews as disease. And so the Nazi extermination pro-

gram was viewed by its perpetrators as a gigantic program in sanitation and public health. It started 

with quarantining the off ending organisms in ghettoes and concentration camps and ended with the 

extermination of those who did not succumb to the “natural” consequences of the quarantine, such 

as the various epidemics and hunger.

RT3340X_C007.indd   98

RT3340X_C007.indd   98

7/11/2006   9:46:42 AM

7/11/2006   9:46:42 AM


99

Abortion and Disability

Yet a measure of selection was practiced throughout the eradication process: It was still Auslese as 

well as Ausmerze. At every step choices were made of who could still be used and who had become 

“worthless.” We have read the books and seen the fi lms that show selections being made as the cattle 

cars emptied the victims into the concentration camps: to work or to die? Th

  at is where Joseph Mengele, 

an M. D./Ph. D., selected the twins and other unfortunates to use as subjects for his scientifi c experi-

ments at Auschwitz, performed in collaboration with Professor von Verschuer, at that time director 

of the Kaiser Wilhelm Institute for Anthropology, Human Genetics, and Eugenics in Berlin. And von 

Verschuer was not the only distinguished scientist who gratefully accepted the human tissues and body 

fl uids provided by Mengele. Aft er the war it became fashionable to characterize the experiments as 

“bad science,” but as Beno Müller-Hill (1984) emphasizes, nothing about them would be considered 

“bad” were they done with mice. What was “bad” was not their scientifi c content but the fact that they 

were being done with “disenfranchised human beings” (p. 97).

Prenatal Testing: Who Should Inhabit the World?

I want to come back to the present, but I needed to go over this history in order to put my misgiv-

ings and those of some of the Germans who are opposing genetic testing into the proper perspective. 

I can phrase the problem best by rephrasing a question Hannah Arendt asks in the epilogue of her 

commentary on the trial of Adolf Eichmann. Who has the “right to determine who should and who 

should not inhabit the world?” (1977). Th

  at’s what it comes down to.

So let me be clear: I am not suggesting that prenatal diagnosis followed by abortion is similar to 

euthanasia. Fetuses are not people. And a woman must have the right to terminate her pregnancy, 

whatever her reasons. I am also not drawing an analogy between what the Nazis did and what we and 

others in many of the industrialized countries are doing now. Because the circumstances are diff erent, 

diff erent things are being done and for diff erent reasons. But a similar eugenic ideology underlies 

what happened then and the techniques now being developed. So it is important that we understand 

how what happened then came about—and not in some faraway culture that is altogether diff erent 

from ours but in the heart of Europe, in a country that has produced artists, writers, composers, philo-

sophers, jurists, scientists, and physicians the equal of any in the Western world. Given that record, 

we cannot aff ord to be complacent.

Scientists and physicians in this and other countries are once more engaged in developing the 

means to decide what lives are worth living and who should and should not inhabit the world. Except 

that now they provide only the tools, while pregnant women themselves have to make the decisions, 

euphemistically called choices. No one is forced to do anything. A pregnant woman must merely 

“choose” whether to terminate a wanted pregnancy because she has been informed that her future 

child will have a disability (although, as I have said before, usually no one can tell her how severe 

the disability will be). If she “chooses” not to take the tests or not to terminate a pregnancy despite a 

positive result, she accepts responsibility for whatever the disability will mean to that child and to her 

and the rest of her family. In that case, her child, her family, and the rest of society can reproach her 

for having so-to-speak “caused” that human being’s physical pain as well as the social pain he or she 

experiences because our society does not look kindly on people with disabilities.

Th

  ere is something terribly wrong with this situation, and although it diff ers in many ways from 



what went wrong in Germany, at base are similar principles of selection and eradication. Lest this 

analogy seem too abstract, let me give a few examples of how the principle of selection and eradica-

tion now works in practice.

Th

  ink of people who have Huntington’s disease; as you may remember they were on the list of people 



to be sterilized in Germany. Huntington’s disease is a degenerative disease of the nervous system and 

is unusual among hereditary diseases in that it is inherited as what geneticists call a dominant trait. 

In other words, even people in whom only one of the pair of genes that is involved with regulating 

the relevant metabolic processes is aff ected manifest the disease. Most other gene-mediated diseases, 

such as Tay-Sachs disease or sickle-cell anemia, are so-called recessives: Only people in whom both 

members of the relevant pair of genes are aff ected manifest the disease. In the case of recessive diseases

RT3340X_C007.indd   99

RT3340X_C007.indd   99

7/11/2006   9:46:43 AM

7/11/2006   9:46:43 AM



Ruth Hubbard

100


people with only one aff ected gene are called carriers: Th

  ey do not have the disease and usually do not 

even know that they carry a gene for it. To inherit a recessive disease such as sickle-cell anemia, a child 

must get an aff ected gene from each of its parents; to inherit a dominant disease, such as Huntington’s 

disease, it is enough is she or he gets an aff ected gene from either parent.

Th

  e symptoms of Huntington’s disease usually do not appear until people are in their thirties, 



forties, or fi ft ies—in other words, aft er most people who want to have children have already had one 

or more. Woody Guthrie had Huntington’s disease, but he did not become ill until aft er he had lived 

a varied and productive life, produced a large legacy of songs, and fathered his children. At present, 

there is no cure for Huntington’s disease, although scientists have been working to fi nd one. However, 

a test has been developed that makes it possible to establish with fair reliability whether a person or 

fetus carries the gene for Huntington’s disease, provided a suffi

  cient number of people in that family 

is willing to be tested.

Th

  e existence of this test puts people with a family history of Huntington’s disease in an outrageous 



position: Although they themselves are healthy and do not know whether they will get the disease, 

they must decide whether to be tested, whether to persuade as many of their relatives as possible to 

do the same, and whether to test their future child prenatally so they can terminate the pregnancy 

if the test reveals that the fetus has the gene for Huntington’s disease. If it does and they decide on 

abortion, they are as much as saying that a life lived in the knowledge that one will eventually die of 

Huntington’s disease is not worth living. What does that say about their own life and the lives of their 

family members who now know that they have the gene for Huntington’s disease? If the fetus has the 

gene and they do not abort, they are knowingly wishing a cruel, degenerative disease on their future 

child. And if they refuse the test, they can be accused of sticking their heads in the sand. Th

  is is an 

obscene “choice” for anyone to have to make!

Some other inherited diseases also do not become evident until later in life, such as retinitis pig-

mentosa, a degenerative eye disease. People with this disease are born with normal vision, but their 

eyesight deteriorates, although usually not until midlife, and they may eventually lose their sight. 

(People with this disease presumably also were slated for sterilization by the Nazis because it is a form 

of “hereditary blindness.”) Th

  ere are diff erent patterns of inheritance of retinitis pigmentosa, and 

prenatal diagnosis is becoming available for one of these patterns and being sought for others. What 

are prospective parents to do when confronted with the “choice” of aborting a pregnancy because 

their future child may become blind at some time during its life?

Another, rather diff erent, problem arises with regard to the so-called neural-tube defects (NTDs), a 

group of developmental disorders which, in fact, are not inherited. Th

  ey include anencephaly (failure 

to develop a brain) and spina bifi da (failure of the spinal column, and sometimes also the overlying 

tissues, to close properly) Babies with anencephaly die before birth or shortly thereaft er. Th

 e severity 

of the health problems of children who have spina bifi da depends on where along the spinal column 

the defect is located and can vary from life-threatening to relatively mild. Th

  e incidence of NTDs varies 

geographically and tends to be higher in industrialized than in nonindustrialized areas. Women who 

carry a fetus with a neural-tube defect have a grater than usual concentration of a specifi c substance, 

called alpha-feto-protein, in their blood. A blood test has been developed to detect NTDs prenatally, 

and California now requires that all pregnant women in the state be off ered this test. Th

 e women 

are fi rst counseled about NTDs and about the test and then have to sign a consent or refusal form. 

If they refuse, that is the end of it. If they consent, they can later refuse to abort the fetus even if the 

test is positive. Th

  is procedure sounds relatively unproblematical, although the requirement to sign 

a refusal form is coercive. (You cannot walk away; you must say no.) Th

  e trouble is that although the 

test detects virtually all fetuses who have NTDs, it yields a large number of false positive results that 

suggest that the fetus has a NTD although it does not.

Let us look at some numbers. In California there are about two hundred thousand births a year 

RT3340X_C007.indd   100

RT3340X_C007.indd   100

7/11/2006   9:46:43 AM

7/11/2006   9:46:43 AM


101

Abortion and Disability

and the incidence of NTDs is about one per thousand. So, about 200 pregnant women a year carry 

fetuses with NTDs and 199,800 do not. However, about 5 percent of women test positive on a fi rst 

test. In other words, if all pregnant women agreed to be tested, 10,000 women would have a positive 

test, 9,800 of which would be false positives. Th

  ose 10,000 women would then have to undergo the 

stress of worrying as well as further tests in order to determine who among them is in fact carrying 

a fetus with a NTD. And no test will tell the 200 women whose fetus, in fact, has a NTD how severe 

their child’s health problem will be. All this testing with uncertain results must be off ered at this time, 

when health dollars in California, as elsewhere, have been cut to the bone, and increasing numbers of 

pregnant women are coming to term with little or no prenatal services of any sort.

Th

  e reason I have spelled this problem out in such detail is to make it clear that in many of these 



situations parents have only the most tenuous basis for making their decisions. Because of the fear of 

raising a child with a serious disability, many women “choose” to abort a wanted pregnancy if they are 

told that there is any likelihood whatever that their future child may have a health problem. At times 

like that we seem to forget that we live in a society in which every day people of all ages are disabled 

by accidents—at work, on the street, or at home—many of which could be prevented if the neces-

sary money were spent, the necessary precautions taken. What is more, because of the deteriorating 

economic conditions of poor people and especially women, increasing numbers of babies are born 

with disabilities that could easily be prevented and are prevented in most other industrialized na-

tions. I question our excessive preoccupation with inherited diseases while callousness and economic 

mismanagement disable and kill increasing numbers of children and adults.

To say again, I am not arguing against a woman’s right to abortion. Women must have that right 

because it involves a decision about our bodies and about the way we will spend the rest of our lives. 

But for scientists to argue that they are developing these tests out of concern for the “quality of life” 

of future children is like the arguments about “lives not worth living.” No one can make that kind of 

decision about someone else. No one these days openly suggests that certain kinds of people be killed; 

they just should not be born. Yet that involves a process of selection and a decision about what kinds 

of people should and should not inhabit the world.

German women, who know the history of Nazi eugenics and how genetic counseling centers func-

tioned during the Nazi period, have organized against the new genetic and reproductive technologies 

(Duelli Klein, Corea, and Hubbard, 1985). Th

  ey are suspicious of prenatal testing and counseling 

centers because some of the scientists and physicians working in them are the same people who de-

signed and implemented the eugenics program during the Nazi period. Others are former co-workers 

or students of these Nazi professors.

Our history is diff erent, but not diff erent enough. Eugenic thinking is part of our heritage and so 

are eugenic sterilizations. Here they were not carried over to mass exterminations because we live in 

a democracy with constitutional safeguards. But, as I mentioned before, even in recent times black, 

Hispanic, and Native-American women have been sterilized against their wills (Rodriguez-Trias, 1982). 

We do not exalt the body of the people, as a collective, over that of individuals, but we come danger-

ously close to doing so when we question the “right” of parents to bear a child who has a disability or 

when we draw unfavorable comparisons between the costs of care for children with disabilities and 

the costs of prenatal diagnosis and abortion. We come mighty close when we once again let scientists 

and physicians make judgments about who should and who should not inhabit the world and applaud 

them when they develop the technologies that let us implement such judgments. Is it in our interest 

to have to decide not just whether we want to bear a child but what kind of children to bear? If we 

try to do that we become entirely dependent on the decisions scientists and physicians make about 

what technologies to develop and what disabilities to “target.” Th

  ose decisions are usually made on 

grounds of professional interest, technical feasibility, and economic and eugenic considerations, not 

out of a regard for the needs of women and children.

RT3340X_C007.indd   101

RT3340X_C007.indd   101

7/11/2006   9:46:43 AM

7/11/2006   9:46:43 AM



Ruth Hubbard

102


Problems with Selective Abortion

I want to be explicit about how I think a woman’s right to abortion fi ts into this analysis and about some 

of the connections I see between what the Nazis did and what is happening now. I repeat: A woman 

must have the right to abort a fetus, whatever her reasons, precisely because it is a decision about her 

body and about how she will live her life. But decisions about what kind of baby to bear inevitably are 

bedeviled by overt and unspoken judgments about which lives are “worth living.”

Nazi eugenic practices were fairly coercive. Th

  e state decided who should not inhabit the world, 

and lawyers, physicians, and scientists provided the justifi cations and means to implement these 


Download 5.02 Mb.

Do'stlaringiz bilan baham:
1   ...   14   15   16   17   18   19   20   21   ...   61




Ma'lumotlar bazasi mualliflik huquqi bilan himoyalangan ©fayllar.org 2024
ma'muriyatiga murojaat qiling