Laclau and Mouffe: The Radical Democratic Imaginary
Download 0.72 Mb. Pdf ko'rish
|
The-Radical-Democratic-Imaginary-oleh-Laclau-and-Mouffe
5 Power and hegemony
1 Chodorow has also been criticized for suggesting that gender difference and feminist social change are primarily concerned with the family and household experience, thereby making it impossible to link the familial institution with economic, political and broad- based socio-cultural relations (Scott 1988:37–8). See also Brown (1995:83), who argues that MacKinnon exaggerates the totalizing and ontologically reductionist dimension of Marx’s theory while failing to adopt its historical and dialectical elements. Hartsock’s theory is similarly limited insofar as it is structured by an analogy with the most reductionist moments in Marx’s theory of ideology (Hartsock 1983:283–5; Marx 1976:42, 67; Barrett 1991:3–17). Hartsock revises her standpoint theory in a later text; she acknowledges, for example, that women are indeed differentiated in terms of class, racial and colonial status (1990:161). Hartsock nevertheless continues to theorize power as a purely negative and external force, and does not address Alarc6n’s challenge concerning intragender antagonisms (1990). Hartsock does refer to the existence of multiple marginalized groups, but she constructs the social as a simple antagonism between two unified blocs—the marginalized and the dominant—without recognizing the persistence of antagonisms among the marginalized and across the marginalized/ dominant divide (1990:171). Finally, she reiterates her basic argument that the social is divided into the rulers and the ruled and that the rulers only have access to a “partial” and “reversed” view of material reality; feminism is again positioned as a superior rational, objective and universal discourse that can unmask false consciousness and recover women’s authentic identities (1990:172). With respect to the general issue of feminist essentialism, it should be noted that many women activists have in fact organized their projects according to a complex understanding of gender that is highly sensitive to class, race and sexual differences throughout the current post-1960s period of feminist mobilization. Part of the problem consists in the fact that insofar as feminists have won mass media attention, the “sound-bite” and “niche-oriented” logic of that coverage is such that only the more binaristic feminist struggles have been featured, while the intersectional and transnational aspects of women’s activism have been ignored (Flanders 1997:4–5). N O T E S 209 2 Zerilli makes a similar point with respect to feminist interpretative strategies. She contends that feminist readings of canonical political theory are inadequate where they merely trace the ways in which the texts in question assign political significance to gendered signifiers, as if the meaning of gendered signifiers were already established elsewhere. Political theorists do not, of course, invent the category of “woman” out of nothing, but they do intervene in gendered discourse in a performative manner. Zerilli aims to bring this constitutive dimension to light: Rather than treat woman either as an embodied social referent or as a term whose meaning preexists its figuration, narrative invocation, and circulation in the political text, I examine woman as she is produced symbolically and deployed rhetorically in theoretical interventions in historical debates about the crisis in political meaning. (1994:4) On the racialized performativity of gender and sexuality discourse in the imperial context, see McClintock (1995) and Stoler (1995). 3 Appiah’s Kantian rationalism, however, yields very little in the way of anti-racist strategies. Where racists resist anti-racist rational dialogue and scientific evidence, Appiah bleakly concludes that they suffer from a “deformation of rationality in judgement,” that may in turn “threaten an agent’s autonomy, making it appropriate to treat or train rather than to reason with them” (1990:9). 4 See, for example, Herrnstein and Murray (1994) and the texts on The Bell Curve, including Devlin et al. (1997), Fischer et al. (1996), Fraser (1995) and Kinchloe et al. (1996). 5 For a critique of The Bell Curve and race-based conclusions from “intelligence testing,” see S.Could (1981), Johnson (1994), Gardner (1994), Holmes (1994), Holt (1994), Lewin (1994), Herbert (1994), Passell (1994), Hirsch (1994), Ryan (1994) and Lane (1994). 6 This critique of Althusser does not, however, amount to an endorsement of Scott’s rejection of hegemony theory. From a Gramscian-Foucauldian perspective, Scott’s argument becomes problematic insofar as he constructs significant formal continuities between radically different formations, such as slavery and late capitalism, and treats the identities of the disempowered as if they were prior to power relations (Scott 1990). 7 Butler notes that although the American judiciary has allowed for an expansion of the category of obscenity, it has consistently rejected the claim that a person of color who has been subjected to racist speech—including cross-burnings—has suffered an injury that would legitimate the abrogation of the First Amendment. Under the First Amendment, speech can be regulated only if it violates the obscenity “community standards,” or if it fails the “clear and present danger” test. By ruling in R.A.V. v. St. Paul (1992) that a burning cross on a black family’s lawn remained protected speech, even though there is a well-documented historical relationship between burning crosses and racist acts of arson and murder in the United States, the Supreme Court effectively drained that deadly historicity out of the burning cross signifier. Butler also demonstrates that some officials regard blacks as the primary source of racially incendiary speech (1997a:62–5). Her critique can be compared in this respect to that of the British leftists who took aim against the British Race Relations Act (1965). Citing the fact that black activists have been charged under this law with the incitement of racial hatred against whites, they have argued that it was designed solely to promote the state’s social control agenda in the name of safeguarding the “public order” (Sivanandan 1982:17–18). N O T E S 210 8 There are, of course, several risks involved in the use of this compassionate discourse. To the extent that Clinton transforms himself into an empathetic figure and uses phrases that are usually found in the context of a discourse between equal members of a therapeutic support group, he decreases the symbolic distance between his office and his constituents, thereby endangering his Presidential stature. In contemporary American society, a successful populist would probably have to move back and forth between the compassionate position and the dignified elder statesman position, thereby symbolically inciting both egalitarian sibling/sibling-style identifications and hierarchical parent/child-style identifications. His critics would point out, in any event, that Clinton has also lost Presidential stature because of his own wrongdoings with respect to campaign finance scandals and Jones’ sexual harassment charge, and that his “downsizing” of the dignity in his office synecdochically represents the general “downsizing” of public institutions and the decline in popular trust in the government. Download 0.72 Mb. Do'stlaringiz bilan baham: |
Ma'lumotlar bazasi mualliflik huquqi bilan himoyalangan ©fayllar.org 2024
ma'muriyatiga murojaat qiling
ma'muriyatiga murojaat qiling