Laclau and Mouffe: The Radical Democratic Imaginary
Towards a definition of radical democratic pluralism
Download 0.72 Mb. Pdf ko'rish
|
The-Radical-Democratic-Imaginary-oleh-Laclau-and-Mouffe
Towards a definition of radical democratic pluralism
As I have noted above, political economy themes have not been given a prominent place in Laclau and Mouffe’s texts. On the basis of their specific remarks and their theoretical horizon, we can nevertheless construct the radical democratic pluralist approach to these issues. In a radical democratic society, there would be equal R E T R I E V I N G D E M O C R A C Y 31 access not only to the material resources necessary for self-development, but also to meaningful participation in social, cultural, political and economic decision- making. The radical democratization of existing state structures and social formations would require a profound redistribution of power and a complete dismantling of the structures that institutionalize inequality, including capitalist exploitation, sexism, homophobia and racism. Today we are also confronted with the rise of transnational corporations and the global restructuration of investment, production and marketing (Barnet and Cavanaugh 1994; Bennis and Moushabeck 1993). This is not to say that there is anything inherently progressive in familiar, “local” or small-scale institutions, but that radical democratization would ultimately require economic transformations and progressive forms of political solidarity on a transnational level. Radical democratic theory must retrieve the most progressive aspects of the liberal democratic and socialist traditions while moving beyond their limitations. In addition to liberal democracy’s basic values of freedom and equality, radical democracy must retrieve from this tradition the concepts of civil liberties and individual self-determination and self-development. For all of Marx’s own attempts to achieve a Hegelian reconciliation between the most positive aspects of individuality and community in a post-capitalist communist society (Avineri 1970:33, 34–7; Elster 1989:151; Marx 1975a:350), many critics argue that he failed to value non-class-based forms of solidarity, human rights, plural conceptions of the good and the permanence of democratic contestation (Femia 1993:65; Bowles and Gintis 1986:18–20; C.Gould 1981:49; Sypnowich 1990:167; Schwartz 1995:21–4, 104–45). While it is true that liberal democracy has often been intertwined with capitalist development, these historical precedents are contingent. For Laclau and Mouffe, the radicalization of the most promising moments of the liberal democratic tradition is entirely possible. Indeed, once the liberal democratic principles of freedom, equality and democracy are radicalized, they can be used to weaken capitalism itself (Cunningham 1987:158–9). These liberal democratic principles therefore have to be both retrieved and radicalized. Eisenstein contends, for example, that we need to transform the liberal feminist conception of the right to privacy. A radicalized approach to privacy would, first, dismantle the interventionist machinery of the state where it pursues authoritarian moralistic and domestic security agendas. But it would also reverse the trend towards state privatization by expanding individual rights to include social rights and by reinvigorating the conception of public responsibility. Eisenstein rejects the shrinkage of the right to privacy to its current status as the right for wealthy women to obtain an abortion through privately insured or financed health care. A meaningful right to privacy would entail universal access to abortion, contraception and childbearing for all women, poor and wealthy alike. It would also embrace the rights of lesbians and gays to organize their personal lives according to their own values without interference or the discriminatory subsidization of heterosexuality on the part of the state. A genuine right to privacy would not just shelter the individual from state interference in the “private” sphere; it would also R E T R I E V I N G D E M O C R A C Y 32 entail the right to live in conditions in which everyone has equal access to the basic resources necessary to make meaningful choices in that protected sphere (Eisenstein 1994:174–5). Laclau and Mouffe’s original contribution to democratic theory—and the specificity of what they call “radical democratic pluralism”—consists in the way in which they combine two apparently contradictory goals together: unity and autonomy. The authors’ fundamental concern is that the imposition of the wrong kinds of unity can limit the democratic potential of the social movements in question 15 . Laclau and Mouffe call for the kind of political strategy that can achieve unity and preserve autonomy at the same time—that is, a radical democratic pluralist hegemonic strategy. They argue that it is only by conceptualizing unity in terms of hegemonic articulation that the goal of unifying different movements becomes compatible with the goal of preserving their autonomy (Laclau and Mouffe 1985:166–7, 178, 181–3, 191). I will discuss the concepts of articulation and hegemony with greater precision in the following chapters. At this point, however, the following outline of their argument can be offered. Laclau and Mouffe want to promote the type of unification of democratic movements that would allow for effective solidarity without asking any individual movement to pay the price of tokenism, co-optation and assimilation. No single struggle should be allowed to impose its agenda over all of the others. While each struggle should learn from the others—it should share political values and tools, engage in collaborative strategies, and reform its identity as it takes on board the democratic demands of the other progressive struggles—it should also continue to develop its own distinctive worldview and pursue its own projects. A leading struggle may emerge; as we will see, Laclau and Mouffe call this the “nodal point” in the radical democratic “hegemonic bloc.” Even where this occurs, however, the leading struggle will be so deeply affected by its negotiations with other progressive struggles that its philosophy, program and tactics—its very identity— would be reshaped in the process. In this sense, each of the democratic struggles would constantly reconstruct their identities through a democratic process of mutual education with the others. This process could not, therefore, be characterized as the formation of a coalition between pre-constituted interest groups. It would take the form instead of continuous negotiations that give rise to new hybrid identities and temporary blocs. Insofar as these negotiations were successful, democratic values would take hold within movements, circulate among different movements and radiate out into new areas of the social. We would witness the further promotion of democracy within each of these struggles and within their corresponding communities, as democratic wisdom would be transmitted across multiple sites. The difficult lessons that are learned in the course of actual political struggles—such as the dangers of charismatic and vanguardist leaderships, the importance of ensuring equal representation to women in decision-making, the value of examining racial privilege and racial exclusion, the continuing relevance of class analysis, the discriminatory character of heterosexism, and so on—would be traded back and R E T R I E V I N G D E M O C R A C Y 33 forth across heretofore uncrossable boundaries. It should also be noted that this “politicization of identities” presupposes a vibrant civil society that is relatively free from total regulation by the state. In a totalitarian context, democratic forces would have to “de-politicize” identities—in the sense of freeing them from the grip of state apparatuses—before this deeper politicization could take place (The Chicago Cultural Studies Group 1994). The authors summarize their conception of radical democratic pluralism in the following terms: Pluralism is radical only to the extent that each term of this plurality finds within itself the principle of its own validity, without this having to be sought in a transcendent or underlying positive ground for the hierarchy of meaning of them all and the source and guarantee of their legitimacy. And this radical pluralism is democratic to the extent that the autoconstitutivity of each one of its terms is the result of displacements of the egalitarian imaginary. (Laclau and Mouffe 1985:167) For Laclau and Mouffe, the irreducibly plural character of the social must be preserved, even as democratic struggles combine to fight authoritarianism. Plurality and diversity are not problems to be overcome; the promotion of those differences that do not contradict liberty and equality is the very condition for the expansion of the democratic revolution (Laclau and Mouffe 1985:166). This argument could be extended further. The diversity among democratic differences must be affirmed as a good in itself; minority groups should never be asked to pay the price of cultural self-destruction through assimilation and disciplinary neutralization in exchange for inclusion, legitimacy and recognition. Genuine “tolerance” must mean that minority groups are granted access to the material resources that they need to preserve their rights and to promote their distinct democratic differences. Genuine “multiculturalism” must mean not only the addition of minority democratic values, but also the opening up of the values held by the majority to the minorities’ democratic critique, and the construction of a new set of shared community values through negotiation. Immigration programs that rate the eligibility of an applicant on the basis of their conformity with white Western middle-class standards; military policies that promise lesbians and gays inclusion only insofar as we keep our sexual orientation a secret; university structures that add women’s studies or black studies courses to the curriculum without addressing sexism and racism on campus; electoral reforms that extend suffrage to women and people of color while job segregation and “glass ceilings” ensure their over-representation among the unemployed, the poor and the homeless; health care “reforms” that ban abortion funding for women on welfare; elections in a Bosnia that remains “ethnically cleansed” 16 and elections in a Russia that conducts brutal civil war against its own people, would all fail this basic democratic pluralism test. R E T R I E V I N G D E M O C R A C Y 34 Laclau and Mouffe do not, of course, endorse an unlimited promotion of autonomy. They insist that progressive struggles must be united to the extent that they reshape their identities with respect to the others’ demands (Mouffe 1996b: 247). They also impose strict conditions on the value of difference for radical democracy. Difference should be celebrated as a positive good, but only insofar as difference does not promote domination and inequality (Mouffe 1992a:13). This qualification has several implications. Every social movement will have many different political variants, for the political value of a movement is not naturally determined by its structural location, but by the way in which it combines different political values together (Laclau and Mouffe 1985:168–9). Laclau and Mouffe would reject, for example, Gitlin’s and Hobsbawm’s argument that environmental politics are inherently “universalist” in contrast to the inherent “particularism” of race, gender and sexuality politics (Gitlin 1995:101; Hobsbawm 1996:45); ecological demands can be phrased in either reactionary or progressive terms. Protection for the environment can be defined, for example, in a racist manner. Some environmentalists have failed to respect the land claims of the aboriginal peoples, while others have embraced population control for the poor in developing countries 17 and immigration control in the developed world as policies necessary for the protection of the ecology from excessive pressure. Environmentalists can also define their struggle in an anti-capitalist manner, such that it primarily targets corporate profiteering. For radical democratic pluralism, only those fragments of the social movements that uphold democratic principles should be valued as progressive differences. Furthermore, reactionary social elements commonly appropriate the discourse of civil rights movements in their demands for the protection of their “special ways of life.” Again, respect for autonomy should be extended only to those groups and movements that value liberty and equality. Demands for multicultural programs that would preserve the cultural symbols of the pro-slavery American south, and demands for affirmative action for right-wing religious extremists, should be dismissed as fraudulent claims. For Laclau and Mouffe, the political meaning of environmentalism, civil rights and every other social struggle is open to contestation; the task for the Left is to engage in a political battle to bend their meaning in a radical democratic pluralist direction. Radical democratic pluralism attacks all forms of domination and holds disciplinary normalization in suspicion; it takes aim at anti-democratic economic institutions, state apparatuses, social structures and cultural practices alike while it works with the democratic elements that are scattered throughout the social; it welcomes democratic forms of diversity, activism, innovation and dissent; and above all, it seeks to deepen and to broaden the advance of freedom and equality. The task for radical democratic pluralism is “to struggle against autocratic power in all its forms in order to infiltrate the various spaces still occupied by non- democratic centers of power” (Mouffe 1993b:94). The fact that we are now at a great distance from genuine democracy is sobering but not devastating for radical democratic theory and practice. The achievement of close approximations to R E T R I E V I N G D E M O C R A C Y 35 radical democratic pluralism is both feasible and desirable. Imperfect democracy should always be valued over an even more imperfect democracy, for the greater the degree of democracy, the greater the degree of freedom, and an increase in democracy always creates favorable conditions for greater democratization in the future (Cunningham 1987:55, 60). Download 0.72 Mb. Do'stlaringiz bilan baham: |
Ma'lumotlar bazasi mualliflik huquqi bilan himoyalangan ©fayllar.org 2024
ma'muriyatiga murojaat qiling
ma'muriyatiga murojaat qiling