Laclau and Mouffe: The Radical Democratic Imaginary
Download 0.72 Mb. Pdf ko'rish
|
The-Radical-Democratic-Imaginary-oleh-Laclau-and-Mouffe
function of identification as such—the latter being independent of any
content and linked to the former only in a contingent way. (Laclau and Zac 1994:35) According to this analysis, it is primarily the formal character of a political discourse that makes it a compelling site of identification. “One approves of the Law because it is Law, not because it is rational. In a situation of radical disorganization there is a need for an order, and its actual contents become a secondary consideration” (Laclau 1994:3). In a moment of organic crisis, one becomes acutely aware of the dislocation in the structure, in the sense that one has “an ‘experience’ which makes visible the ultimate contingency of all forms of identification” (Norval 1996:13). Craving order, we become extremely vulnerable during a crisis to political discourses that promise to restore coherence first by offering themselves as myths—concrete readings of the otherwise unintelligible crisis—and later by offering themselves as F R O M L E N I N T O G R A M S C I 77 imaginaries—horizons of intelligibility. Laclau’s central argument is that there is nothing in the materiality of an organic crisis or a dislocation in the structure that predetermines which political discourse will prevail in this manner. At the center of a crisis—where we might expect an embryonic substance that will reveal itself as the necessary solution—there is actually nothing but a radical indeterminacy, emptiness or lack. The moment of dislocation in the structure is not just a weak point; it is a radical absence. In Laclau’s terms, this process of becoming caught up in one identification rather than another is a “decision” that is taken in the (non-)space in which the structure has failed, for our choice is ultimately contingent, rather than determined in advance. The subject is partially “self-determined” in the sense that it is “condemned” to take a decision in conditions that Derrida describes as the “ordeal of the undecidable” (Laclau 1996c:53). This moment of “self-determination,” however, should not be understood as a voluntarist expression of a preconstituted interest, for it is produced out of a fundamental absence, namely the failure of the structure to constitute fully the being of the subject. Laclau asserts that the “subject equals the pure form of the structure’s dislocation, of its ineradicable distance from itself” (1990a:60). The subject never exists as a fully self-conscious actor who can stand back from her historical embeddedness, obtain total clarity about her condition, and instrumentally select one alternative among many according to her already-determined set of preferences. As Nietzsche puts it,” ‘the doer’ is merely a fiction added to the deed” (1969:45). Nor is the subject merely the vehicle of an omnipotent historical force or all-encompassing totality, such that all of her decisions are always already determined. Laclau’s argument can be read, then, as a critique of voluntarism, historicism and functionalism. To the extent that Laclau’s position is integrated with the conceptions of the historical trace and overdetermination, it does not collapse into a relativist agnosticism; I will return to this problem in Chapter 3. The selection of one political discourse instead of another in the condition of undecidability is therefore analogous to identification in psychoanalysis, rather than the decision in rational choice theory. If one selection prevails over another in the context of an organic crisis, then that decision is contingent; there is nothing that wholly guarantees that another identification could not have prevailed in its place. With identification, we construct an analogy between political decision- making in undecidable conditions and the struggle of Lacan’s infant in the “mirror stage” to make sense of its chaotic world. Traumatized by the unbearable experience of dislocation, we search for some sort of organizing framework that makes our experience bearable. Lacan’s infant (mis-)takes the image in the mirror as its own self, and the lure of the mirror image that facilitates this substitution consists precisely in its framed and stabilized character. The infant thereby achieves the sense of itself as a coherent totality, but only through (mis-) identification with an external image that remains irreducibly “other.” In this manner, dependence on otherness, alienation, transitivism and paranoiac knowledge are written into the very principle of our subjectivity (Lacan 1977:1–7; Muller and Richardson F R O M L E N I N T O G R A M S C I 78 1982:5–34). From a Lacanian perspective, there is no subject with fully formed desires prior to the decision; there is only a deep anxious need for order. One political discourse will tend to prevail over others, then, to the extent that it effectively promises to provide a “minimum of consistency” (Žižek 1989:75) in an otherwise chaotic terrain. 12 Understood from a psychoanalytic perspective, the “subject” is not the same as “subject positions.” With the psychoanalytic concept of the subject as a subject of lack, we have the principle of the impossibility of identity, for “every identity is already in itself blocked” (Žižek 1990:252). With subject positions, by contrast, we emphasize the ways in which identity plays an interpretative, mediating role - albeit in necessarily imperfect and incomplete forms—in the incitement of certain practices in specific historical contexts. As Norval contends, an emphasis on both dimensions is needed. Subject position theory without the principle of the impossibility of identity could become just another version of functionalism, while the psychoanalytic concept of subjectivity on its own tends to disregard the ways in which social agents are constructed within historically specific networks of power relations (Norval 1996:64). With the emphasis on Lacanian theory in his later work, Laclau has shifted away from his earlier post-structuralist conception of the “articulation” of “floating signifiers.” I will deal with the concept of articulation at length in Chapter 3. At this point, articulation can be loosely defined as follows. Political discourses attempt to give new meaning to key signifiers such as “freedom” or “democracy,” as they struggle to become the interpretative frameworks through which we live our structural positionings. In Hegemony and Socialist Strategy (1985), Laclau and Mouffe argue that these struggles over meaning take the form of articulation. “Floating signifiers,” the political concepts that are open to redefinition, are given new meanings as they are combined with other concepts in novel ways. Every articulation is always partial, such that the meaning of these signifiers is never fixed once and for all. However, even when the effects of past articulations are weakened, they are never totally lost; every signifier bears the traces of past articulations (1985:113). Those traces are more akin to Derrida’s “minimal remainders” than essences, in the sense that they never play a fully determining role (Derrida 1988:51–2). The non-determining presence of those traces in every signifier that is available for articulation nevertheless means that it is never purely empty, never purely open to the assignment of just any meaning. With the concept of the articulation of “floating signifiers,” Laclau and Mouffe achieve a remarkable synthesis between the Gramscian and post-structuralist approaches. Their argument about the non-essentialist historical continuities that consistently reassert themselves in unpredictable ways across contingent repetitions draws on both the Gramscian conception of historicity and the Derridean (non-)concept of différance. The tension between Laclau’s earlier and later work can be explained in part with respect to the different arguments in Lacanian and post-structuralist theory on the question of structure, the failure of closure and repetition. While both F R O M L E N I N T O G R A M S C I 79 Lacanians and post-structuralists would agree that every structure—that is, in the respective terms of these two theories, a symbolic order or a discourse—is never completely closed, they disagree on the “structurality” of that openness. For Lacanians, it is the real that constantly interrupts every structure and yet compels the identifications that build up identity-effects and give rise to partial social formations. For Derrideans, by contrast, a structure attempts to spatialize a semantic field. A structure aims to achieve totality-effects; it strives to appear and to operate as if it did have a fixed center and an unbroken ring of borders at its circumference. To the extent that this process is successful, the discourse in question actually does begin to have structuring effects; the signifier that poses as a center becomes a defining point for contiguous elements, its apparent boundaries begin to exercise border effects, and so on. Deconstruction aims precisely to demonstrate the concealed processes that simultaneously make this spatializing effect possible, and yet fundamentally and necessarily open every structure to différence: the movement of difference that cannot be domesticated (Gasché 1986:143–7). Deconstructive criticism may decenter structure, for example, by showing its hidden dependence on multiple centers; its secret constitutive relation with what is outside the boundaries; its consistent subversion of its own rules as each of its repetitions introduces irreducible differentiation; and so on. For our purposes here, we should note that these two arguments differ in one crucial respect. The real is utterly unsymbolizable; as such, we cannot grasp via any historical logic the relations between the different moments in which the real interrupts the symbolic order. From Žižek’s perspective, each of the traumatic moments in which the real erupts in history are, in a formal sense, equivalent and substitutable (1989:50). Butler suggests that for Žižek, “what is historical and what is traumatic are made absolutely distinct; indeed, the historical becomes what is most indifferent to the question of trauma” (1993:202). 13 It could be further argued that the Lacanian tendency towards formalistic arguments and transhistorical laws flows precisely from this quarantining of historicity. Butler contends, “Žižek’s rendition of the real presupposes that there is an invariant law that operates uniformly in all discursive regimes to produce through prohibition this ‘lack’ that is the trauma induced by the threat of castration, the threat itself” (1993:205). 14 By contrast, post-structuralists insist on the “structured” character of the failure of structure. While deconstruction, like psychoanalysis, holds that a series of moments in which closure becomes impossible cannot be grasped in fully positive terms, it does nevertheless describe these closure-failures as imperfect repetitions. One moment in which closure fails will not only compel a reasserted attempt to achieve closure, it will also partially construct the conditions for the next failure. The contingency that characterizes these transitions—from failure to closure attempt to new failure—is such that we cannot predict exactly how they will proceed, but we can retroactively describe the traces or family resemblances that cut in and out of these moments, and suggest various possibilities for future iterations. F R O M L E N I N T O G R A M S C I 80 In Butler’s commentary on Laclau’s Derridean conception of articulation, she writes, “to take up the political signifier…is to be taken into a chain of prior usages, to be installed in the midst of significations that cannot be situated in terms of clear origins or ultimate goals” (1993:219). Further, Butler describes this chain of citations as an “iterable practice that shows that what one takes to be a political signifier is itself the sedimentation of prior signifiers” (1993:220). Each citational moment reworks the signifier, mobilizing the “phantasmatic promise” that was integral to past citations—namely the promise to deliver order and completion—and yet simultaneously reconstructing those past articulations such that the signifier also promises “‘the new,’ a ‘new’ that is itself only established through recourse to those embedded conventions, past conventions, that have conventionally been invested with the political power to signify the future” (1993:220). Butler agrees with Žižek that the subject is never coherent and self- identical because it is founded on a series of exclusions—refusals, repudiations, repressions, abjections, and so on—and that every political signifier will necessarily fail to deliver on its promise of order and completion. She nevertheless differs with him on the historical character of that failure. The “failure” of the signifier to produce the unity it appears to name is not the result of an existential void, but the result of that term’s incapacity to include the social relations that it provisionally stabilizes through a set of contingent exclusions. This incompleteness will be the result of a specific set of social exclusions that return to haunt the claims of identity defined through negation; these exclusions need to be read and used in the reformulation and expansion of a democratizing reiteration of the term. (1993:221) Butler therefore acknowledges the openness of the structure while insisting on the historical specificity of the instances in which the failure of completion takes place. Further, this approach does have concrete implications for democratic political practice. Butler is, in a sense, calling for the interpretation of what Gramsci would call the organic character of constitutive exclusions and the deployment of that historicizing interpretation in the construction of counter-articulations. The non-essentialist repetition principle—what Derrida calls “iteration” (1988)—and the concept of political signifiers in current articulations as always bearing the non-determining traces of past articulations, has been relatively de- emphasized in Laclau’s recent work. In a co-authored article published in 1994, Laclau and Zac state that “terms such as ‘the unity of the people’, the ‘welfare of the Download 0.72 Mb. Do'stlaringiz bilan baham: |
Ma'lumotlar bazasi mualliflik huquqi bilan himoyalangan ©fayllar.org 2024
ma'muriyatiga murojaat qiling
ma'muriyatiga murojaat qiling