Laclau and Mouffe: The Radical Democratic Imaginary
Articulation, equivalence and difference
Download 0.72 Mb. Pdf ko'rish
|
The-Radical-Democratic-Imaginary-oleh-Laclau-and-Mouffe
Articulation, equivalence and difference
From Laclau and Mouffe’s perspective, political identities are analogous to Saussure’s linguistic signs. Like Saussure, they reject a referential theory of identity in favor of an exclusively relational theory. Political discourses and identities are wholly constituted through articulation, which they define as “any practice establishing a relation among elements such that their identity is modified as a result of the articulatory practice” (Laclau and Mouffe 1985:105). An articulation consists of the transformative combination of two or more discursive elements. As we saw in Chapter 1, for example, socialism is not necessarily democratic, but a socialist project can indeed become democratic insofar as it is articulated with—that is, transformed through its combination with—democratic discourse. In Chapter 2, we considered an imaginary example in which three different individuals live their structural positions as workers through the neo-conservative, religious fundamentalist and democratic leftist subject positions. Having looked at what subject positions do, we should now consider the ways in which subject positions are constituted. Each of the subject positions are like “floating signifiers”: their meaning is never entirely fixed but always remains open to change. The meaning of a subject position is constructed through its differential relations with the other subject positions that are found in a given discursive formation (Laclau and Mouffe 1985:113). Following Barker (1981), for example, we could distinguish between two basic types of racism: traditional racism on the one hand, and cultural racism or the “new racism” on the other. While traditional racism explicitly affirms the superiority of the white Anglo Saxon race, the new racism gives its support to the same segregationist politics, but defends the latter as the only public policy that adequately expresses recognition of cultural differences. The traditional racist subject position became meaningful through its differential relations with similar and opposed subject positions, such as social Darwinism, eugenics, and anti- Semitism on the one hand, and universalist humanism on the other. Although traditional racism became a widely accepted discourse in the West through the nineteenth and early twentieth centuries, it did not fix the meaning of racism for all time. A new discourse that opposed racism gained authority, namely cultural relativism. As the latter became normalized, the value of traditional racism changed, for it became largely discredited. Post-colonial racists, however, soon appropriated key elements out of cultural relativism and constructed a new cultural racism. Because their racism mimics the normalized features of cultural relativism, the post-colonial racists were able to pose as anti-racists. T H E S U B V E R S I O N O F E S S E N T I A L I S M 88 In short, what we have in this example is a complex field of different interpretative frameworks, or subject positions, in which the meaning of each subject position is shaped by its differential relations with the others. The study of the differential construction of a subject position becomes all the more complicated when the constitutive role of absent subject positions is taken into account. A taboo, for example, might preclude the explicit articulation of a signifier—this may be the case, for example, where abject feminine, homosexual or racially “other” signifiers are concerned—but that may not prevent it from shaping the meaning of other signifiers in an invisible manner. Discourse analysis cannot stop short at the interpretation of the subject positions that a discursive formation openly avows; it must always perform genealogies of erasure and archaeologies of silence as well (Sedgwick 1990; Hammonds 1994:138–9). Saussure contends that the extra-discursive does not determine the constitutive relations between signs. Laclau and Mouffe similarly insist that there is nothing that is meaningful or has being for us outside the discursive. Extra-discursive matter has brute existence but remains fundamentally unknowable for us. We can say nothing positive about pure matter; it is so utterly formless that it even defies description. Again, our discursive attempts to distinguish between the discursive and the extra-discursive become impossible, for we inevitably resort to discursively- constituted concepts to refer to the extra-discursive (Butler 1993:31). In the examples presented in Chapter 2, we considered different subject positions in isolation. In actual political situations, identity is always overdetermined in the psychoanalytic sense. Overdetermination entails not only a plurality of causal factors, but also a certain degree of irreducibility. A dream, for example, is the product of condensation whereby various different unconscious elements are merged together such that they give rise to a single manifest sequence. However, even if we could isolate each of those constitutive elements, we could not say that their combination necessarily produced this specific dream, for their mutually constitutive convergence could have produced several other meaningful sequences as well (Laplanche and Pontalis 1973:292–3). The identity of an individual, group or movement is also in this sense a product of condensation: it is always the product of an irreducible plurality of subject positions. Insofar as the coherence of that plurality is always context dependent, every identity is at least potentially precarious. Each ensemble of subject positions is like an incomplete linguistic system: the value of each subject position is shaped by its relations with the others, but always remains open to the constitutive effects of new differential relations. Consider, for example, the two sides in the affirmative action debate in California during the mid-1990s. The pro-affirmative action side includes civil rights organizations, people of color community organizations, feminist groups, progressive trade unions and the AFL-CIO, student groups and small leftist organizations. On the anti-side, we have the Republican Party, neo-conservatives who oppose what they call “special rights” and “preferential treatment,” anti- feminists, racists who oppose the advance of people of color in any shape or T H E S U B V E R S I O N O F E S S E N T I A L I S M 89 form and xenophobes who see affirmative action as an incentive for non-white immigrants to settle in California. Insofar as these groups form two opposed blocs, the following analysis can be suggested. On each side of the debate, the different subject positions are articulated together to form a chain of equivalence (Laclau and Mouffe 1985:127–9). To the extent that we are dealing with articulation—and not just a superficial coalition—the value of each subject position in the chain is shaped by its relations with the others. Perhaps trade union militancy or radical feminism, for example, would become more multicultural as these subject positions were brought into closer negotiations with progressive anti-racist subject positions during the pro-affirmative action campaign. Ultimately, hegemonic articulation would occur on both a conscious and unconscious level, as anti-racism began to operate as a compelling overarching framework for identification for anti-racists, trade union militants and radical feminists alike. Wherever different subject positions are symbolically located together in opposition to another camp, such that their meanings are subsequently transformed by their overlapping identifications with partially shared sets of beliefs, then we are dealing with an articulated chain of equivalence. We should note, however, that a chain of equivalence never dissolves into a singular homogeneous mass; the differences between the subject positions in question are always to some extent preserved. Taking the chain as a whole, we could say that its identity is constituted by its differential relation with other chains. The meaning of the “pro-affirmative action” movement is defined by the antagonism between itself and its opponent, the “anti- affirmative action” camp. Actual struggles are, of course, extremely complex. Every subject position bears the residual traces of past articulations, and is always being articulated into many different chains of equivalence at the same time. As progressive feminism is active in the pro-affirmative action campaign, its meaning is also being shaped in its campaigns on abortion, sexual harassment and rape, breast cancer, the war against poor women and so on. Further, the negotiations between the different subject positions within one chain of equivalence can be extremely complicated. As I will discuss below, one position, the “nodal point,” can emerge as the position that is predominant in the sense that it has the greatest effect in reshaping the meaning of the other positions in the chain. This is one logic of the social, namely the logic of equivalence (Laclau and Mouffe 1985:129–30). Wherever social forces tend to become organized in terms of an antagonistic relation between two great chains of equivalence, we can describe that form as the logic of equivalence. In some contexts, political forces that have become stabilized in terms of a logic of equivalence representation will be displaced by other forces attempting to impose a logic of difference counter-representation. A struggle to manage difference will ensue, and its dimensions will always remain beyond the conscious grasp of the social agents in question. At some moments, political forces attempt to construct the social as an antagonism-free system of subject positions, and subjects find themselves caught up in a corresponding set of identifications. T H E S U B V E R S I O N O F E S S E N T I A L I S M 90 When the Republican Presidential 1996 campaign, for example, learned during the summer of 1996 that many voters had been offended by the extremism of the religious right, they attempted to adopt a complex strategy to manage the differences at hand. Within the Party, every effort was made to accommodate the extremist demands of the Christian Coalition into the official Party platform. In this moment, the Republican Party constructs America according to the logic of equivalence, as an all-out war between “good” and “evil.” When addressing audiences outside the Party, however, Dole attempted to take the moral high ground and to construct the Republican Party as a site in which Americans from all “walks of life” were welcome and respected. Explicit extremist language about abortion and gay rights was almost completely dropped from Dole’s public discourse, and he waited until his defeat was certain before emphasizing his anti-affirmative action and anti-immigration positions. Women, people of color and the handicapped were prominently featured in the Party’s convention and campaign materials. In this second moment, “America” is no longer represented as two great warring camps; it is depicted instead as a peaceful system of different subject positions. For Laclau and Mouffe, this second representational form is the logic of difference (Laclau and Mouffe 1985:130). These two logics limit one another (Laclau and Mouffe 1985:129–34). No political force can sustain a “total war” construction indefinitely; at some point, the antagonism will either dissolve or be suppressed, and at least some of the subject positions that were formerly at war with one another will be effectively reconstructed as elements within an antagonism-free system of differences. This might occur through some degree of genuine resolution of the antagonism, cooptation, assimilation or the splitting of a subject position into new fragments. On the other hand, it is impossible to suppress antagonisms indefinitely in order to maintain a construction of a social field as a peaceful system of differences. The Christian Coalition, for example, is heavily invested not only in the defeat of the Democratic Party, but in an antagonistic construction of “America.” At some point, the Republican Party’s “big tent” approach and back-room deal-making will alienate key players on the religious right, and they will leave the Party to join movements in which they will be able to wage blatantly right-wing extremist political campaigns. Dole’s campaign ultimately failed, and it did so in part because its linkage between neo-conservatism and religious fundamentalism remained exposed as a fragile and opportunistic coalition. The campaign therefore could not construct Dole’s agenda as a coherent worldview that would operate as a compelling site for popular identifications. Download 0.72 Mb. Do'stlaringiz bilan baham: |
Ma'lumotlar bazasi mualliflik huquqi bilan himoyalangan ©fayllar.org 2024
ma'muriyatiga murojaat qiling
ma'muriyatiga murojaat qiling