Laclau and Mouffe: The Radical Democratic Imaginary
participation in the United States: popular expectations about what governments
Download 0.72 Mb. Pdf ko'rish
|
The-Radical-Democratic-Imaginary-oleh-Laclau-and-Mouffe
participation in the United States: popular expectations about what governments ought to achieve have been dramatically reduced, while popular paranoias about evil forces lurking within state apparatuses have been deliberately promoted. To the extent that more centrist political projects, such as Clinton’s conservative Democratic movement, borrow key strategies from the authoritarian hegemony tradition, we should anticipate a greater tendency on their part towards the neutralization of democratic contestation (Smith 1997a). There is nothing in the contradictions within authoritarianism, however, that will by themselves lead to its decline. Not only can contradictory political discourses remain brutally effective, they can also make their contradictions a source of strength. One of the virtues of Laclau and Mouffe’s redefinition of hegemony— from Gramsci’s vision of an articulated bloc of actual subjects to their conception of the institutionalization of a new horizon, the taken-for-granted background knowledge that supplies the hidden assumptions behind authorized political discourse—is that it allows us to grasp the subtle and complex aspect of hegemony politics. As Hall argued with respect to Thatcherism, an authoritarian hegemonic project only needs to achieve the disorganization of the potential opposition and M U LT I C U LT U R A L D I F F E R E N C E A N D T H E P O L I T I C A L 181 a minimal degree of mobilization such that the regime can pass itself off as the expression of the popular will (Hall 1988a). Gramsci contends that where authoritarian “passive revolutions” have become institutionalized, democratic forces will have to wage a protracted “war of position” and struggle to advance an “expansive hegemony.” Multiple struggles that are plural and contextually sensitive in form will have to be deployed at each of the various sites throughout the social in which the “passive revolution” has become entrenched. Where a “passive revolution” seeks to neutralize the democratic opposition and to construct a simulacrum popular movement while perpetuating structural inequality, an “expansive hegemony” seeks to promote a genuinely democratic mobilization of progressive social movements (Buci-Glucksmann 1979:228–9; Mouffe 1979b:182–3). The Gramscian distinction between “passive revolution” and “expansive hegemony” also allows us to clarify Laclau and Mouffe’s conception of radical democratic pluralism. Authoritarian hegemony aims to achieve a maximum disciplining of difference; even as it pretends to endorse pluralism, it can only promote a pseudo-multiculturalism that is entirely compatible with institutional racism. Radical democratic pluralism, by contrast, attempts to construct the sorts of hegemonic discourses that enhance and promote democratic forms of plurality and difference. Confronted with a plurality of progressive struggles already in motion, it seeks to release each of their democratic potentials, while bringing them together in mutually constitutive articulatory relations. It values the autonomy of each struggle, not only as a good in itself, but also for its practical value. In many cases, autonomy facilitates the sort of contextually specific contestation of oppression and exploitation that is needed in today’s complex and hybrid social formations. Further, it values the promotion of hybridized democratic identities, for “hybridization does not necessarily mean decline through the loss of identity: it can also mean empowering existing identities through the opening of new possibilities” (Laclau 1996e:65). Where authoritarian hegemony strictly regulates the development of political contestation, radical democratic pluralist hegemony multiplies the points of contestation and seeks to broaden the terrain of politicization or reactivation (Laclau 1996d:99). The universalistic effects of the radical democratic pluralist horizon tend to institutionalize deeper and deeper recognition of the plurality and autonomy of the public spaces created by democratic struggles. To the extent that the specific discourses of the relatively autonomous progressive struggles are successfully articulated with a radical civic sense, the multiplication of these public spaces becomes a source of strength for a democratizing society (Laclau 1996b:120–1). If authoritarian hegemony has a fundamentally contradictory structure, radical democratic pluralist hegemony has a paradoxical central principle: the more that we advance towards its realization, the more impossible its realization becomes. Radical democratic pluralism is a good that remains a good only insofar as it is not fully institutionalized (Mouffe 1993b:4, 6). The challenge of radical democratic pluralism is that it must gain strategic ground not only by subverting dominant M U LT I C U LT U R A L D I F F E R E N C E A N D T H E P O L I T I C A L 182 institutions, but by founding and defending new ones as well. At the same time, it must guard against the potential that is inherent in its own institutions simply because they are institutions, namely the bureaucratization and disciplining of the social according to exclusionary principles. In a radical democratic pluralist movement, the definition of the good life must always be kept open to contestation; “nothing is definitely acquired and there is always the possibility of challenge” (Laclau 1996d:100). No blueprint for an ideal society could fully grasp all of the exclusions that are built into contemporary institutions and anticipate the unintentional anti-democratic effects of apparently democratic strategies. We can only begin to imagine subjects who have yet to be invented, let alone their rights and responsibilities in communities that will only faintly resemble our own. Democratic activists of all kinds from only a few centuries ago would be bewildered by contemporary democratic politics. We have no reason to assume that we are peculiarly endowed with an ability to make all contemporary and future antagonisms transparent. A space for permanent democratic dissent must therefore be built into the radical democratic pluralist imaginary, for it is through contestation and struggle that exclusions can be brought to light and new democratic institutions can be imagined and established. This point can be illustrated with reference to the debate on multicultural curricula. Radical multicultural educators are not arguing that we ought to include works by women, gays, blacks, Latino/as, Asians, indigenous people and peoples of the Third World in the Western “canon” because they are the only texts that are meaningful for our minority students. Their argument is that traditions of resistance among oppressed and excluded peoples have built up tremendous resources of wisdom, and that that wisdom is embedded within minority discourses. As Gutmann contends, “There are books by and about women, African-Americans, Asian-Americans, and Native Americans that speak to neglected parts of our heritage and human condition, and speak more wisely than do some of the canonical works” (1992:18). Shohat and Stam similarly assert that their “polycentric multiculturalism” “grants an ‘epistemological advantage’ to those prodded by historical circumstances into what W.B. DuBois has called ‘double consciousness,’ to those obliged to negotiate both ‘margins’ and ‘center’ (or even with many margins and many centers), and thus somewhat better placed to ‘deconstruct’ dominant or narrowly national discourses” (1994:48–9). Alexander and Mohanty, citing Moya, also claim an “epistemological advantage” for the oppressed, but insist on the mediating role of interpretation. The experience of repression can be, but is not necessarily, a catalyst for organizing. It is, in fact, the interpretation of that experience from within a collective context that marks the moment of transformation from perceived contradictions and material disenfranchisement to participation in women’s movements. (1997:xl) M U LT I C U LT U R A L D I F F E R E N C E A N D T H E P O L I T I C A L 183 Structural positioning in itself does not guarantee a political outcome; it is only when the experience of oppression is organized in terms of the interpretative framework that is provided by radical subject positions that subversive texts and practices are produced. Further, a radical multicultural curriculum does not embrace any kind of separatism, for it aims to raise students’ awareness about the constitutive relations between different cultures. For Shohat and Stam, polycentric multiculturalism is reciprocal, dialogical; it sees all acts of verbal or cultural exchange as taking place not between discrete bounded individuals or cultures but rather between permeable, changing individuals and communities. Within an ongoing struggle of hegemony and resistance, each act of cultural interlocution leaves both interlocutors changed. (1994:49) Shohat and Stam extend their radical approach into their critique of Eurocentrism. Such a critique would remain conservative if it depicted Europe as a naturally distinct entity unmarked by political struggle and internal and external exclusions; constructed Europeans as a singular people bound together by a homogeneous and timeless cultural tradition; and represented European power as an omnipotent evil capable of achieving total victory on a global scale. Within their approach, an anti-Eurocentric multiculturalism also has to attend to the hybrid differences and complicated histories that constitute Europe itself (1994:4). In this sense, Shohat and Stam (1984) reproduce Bernal’s radical intervention; the point is not merely to find hybridity and difference on the margins, but to interrupt the metropole’s foundational myths as well. Multiculturalism, according to then Modern Language Association President Stimpson, is the “necessary recognition that we cannot think of culture unless we think of many cultures at the same time” (Levine 1996:143). As Levine indicates, radical multiculturalism studies women, immigrants, workers, lesbians and gays and racial minorities not just to bring ethnic and gender difference into our curricula, but to promote a better understanding of socio-economic power. It is crucial to study and understand as many of the contributing cultures and their interactions with one another as possible, not as a matter of “therapeutic” history, as the opponents of multiculturalism keep insisting, not to placate or flatter minority groups and make them feel good, as they also assert, but as a simple matter of understanding the nature and complexities of American culture and the process by which it came, and continues to come, into being. (Levine 1996:160) Even a society that approaches radical democratic pluralism will tend to institutionalize a specific way of thinking; the danger is that domination will become M U LT I C U LT U R A L D I F F E R E N C E A N D T H E P O L I T I C A L 184 normalized and the democratic wisdom at the margins of the social will not be heard. It is only through permanent contestation that every “canon”—even the most apparently radical “canon”—will be constantly exposed to democratic challenges. Against Habermas, who constructs power-free communication as a regulative ideal, Laclau and Mouffe affirm the permanence of power relations. Although Rorty wants to expand the community of “we liberals” through persuasion and the incitement of solidarity-oriented sentiment, rather than argumentation that seeks to ground itself exclusively on context-independent rationality, he also places far too much faith on the construction of consensus, and fails to grasp the practical value of perpetual contestation (Mouffe 1996a:8). In the spirit of Gramsci’s centaur metaphor, Laclau and Mouffe argue that every form of communication, including persuasion, negotiation, and dialogue, is necessarily intertwined with power relations, and that this would remain true in any possible society. Like all post- structuralists, they hold that we cannot ground our ethical decisions in a necessary foundation; every political position that we take is in this sense contingent. Again, this is not to endorse relativism: since our choices are always conditioned by normative traditions, we never inhabit a space in which all the choices before us have equal validity. The traditions that shape our normative decision-making are the residual effects of contingent political struggles. This means that every normative decision taken within historical traditions—traditions that are only Download 0.72 Mb. Do'stlaringiz bilan baham: |
Ma'lumotlar bazasi mualliflik huquqi bilan himoyalangan ©fayllar.org 2024
ma'muriyatiga murojaat qiling
ma'muriyatiga murojaat qiling