Leonid Zhmud The Origin of the History of Science in Classical Antiquity
Download 1.41 Mb. Pdf ko'rish
|
The Origin of the History of Science in
History 1, 175f.
159 Knorr. AT, 15f. 160 He shared also some astronomical views of the Pythagoreans (cf. 41 A 10 and 58 B 37c). 161 Szabó, Á., Maula, E. EGKLIMA. Untersuchungen zur Frühgeschichte der antiken griechischen Astronomie, Geographie und Sehnentafeln, Athens 1982, 118f. It is worth noting that IV, 16 differs somewhat from other propositions of this book. In all of them, the construction of a polygon is followed by a proof that the constructed fig- ure does possess the required qualities. Such proof is lacking in the case of IV, 16 (Neuenschwander. VB, 374). Chapter 5: The history of geometry 202 fr. 6 Lanata), to whom he probably owed his vast knowledge in mathematics. 162 Democritus, who asserted that “nobody excelled him in drawing lines with proofs”, was the author of about ten mathematical works. 163 It is difficult, then, to find any reason why Eudemus should have omitted him from his History of Geometry. If my hypothesis is true, he considered Democritus to be the author of propositions that the cone is equal to one-third of the cylinder and the pyra- mid to one-third of the prism with the same base and height (Eucl. XII, 7 and 10), while noting at the same time that the scientific demonstration of these the- orems was given by Eudoxus. 164 The level of geometry in ca. 440–430 is better appreciated, not from the scant information about Oenopides and Democritus, but rather from the non- trivial problems of duplicating the cube and squaring the circle studied by Hippocrates of Chios, a younger contemporary and probably a student of Oe- nopides. These problems found responses outside the circle of geometers as well. In the Republic we find some hints at duplicating the cube, which later gave rise to a legend about Plato’s part in solving this problem (3.4). Whereas Aristotle remained indifferent to it, Eudemus attests the achievements of Hip- pocrates and cites the solutions offered by Archytas, Eudoxus, and his stu- dents. The problem of squaring the circle aroused still greater interest in wide circles: Aristophanes mentioned it ( Av. 1004–1010), it preoccupied Antiphon and Bryson, and Aristotle often referred to it. 165 The latter circumstance at- tracted to the problem the attention of Aristotle’s commentators Alexander and Simplicius, who brought to us Eudemus’ evidence on Antiphon and Hip- pocrates. In the first case, Eudemus follows Aristotle’s judgment: Antiphon does not admit the basic principles of geometry, in particular, that geometrical magnitudes are infinitely divisible. 166 Unlike Aristotle, however, who accused Hippocrates of having committed a logical mistake by squaring the circle with the help of lunes ( SE 171b 12f.; Phys. 185a 14f.), Eudemus found no fault with him. 167 162 Zhmud. Wissenschaft, 40 n. 69. One of Democritus’ works is related to irrational lines – the problem that only the Pythagoreans had treated before him. Democritus wrote a book on Pythagoras (14 A 6 = fr. 154 Luria). 163 68 B 299 = fr. 137 Luria. The list of mathematical writings by Democritus includes works on geometry, arithmetic, astronomy, and the theory of perspective (D. L. IX, 47–48). 164 See above, 177, and 68 B 155 on the cutting of a cone by parallel planes. Cf. fr. 125 Luria with commentary; Waschkies, op. cit., 267ff. 165 Cat. 7b 31, APr 69a 30–34, APo 75b 40f., SE 171b 13–172a 8, Phys. 185a 16f., EE 1226a 29. 166 Fr. 140, p. 59, 9–12 Wehrli. For a modern appraisal of Antiphon’s approach, see Heath. Download 1.41 Mb. Do'stlaringiz bilan baham: |
Ma'lumotlar bazasi mualliflik huquqi bilan himoyalangan ©fayllar.org 2024
ma'muriyatiga murojaat qiling
ma'muriyatiga murojaat qiling