Leonid Zhmud The Origin of the History of Science in Classical Antiquity
Download 1.41 Mb. Pdf ko'rish
|
The Origin of the History of Science in
Aristarchus, 19; Bicknell, op. cit., 59; KRS, 156; Wöhrle, G. Wer entdeckte
die Quelle des Mondlichts?, Hermes 123 (1995) 244–247. Cf. Boll. Finsternisse, 2342. 113 13 A 7, 13. The order in which the sun, moon, and planets were arranged in his sys- tem is unknown. 114 Pl. Crat. 409a–b = 59 A 76, see also 59 B 8, A 77 and below, 256 n. 117. Chapter 7: The history of astronomy 256 taken to mean that the moon shines by ‘borrowed light’, 115 Parmenides’ cos- mology, due to his “intentional use of ambiguity”, hardly has a chance of being reliably reconstructed. 116 Even if Theophrastus credited him with the idea that the moon’s light is received from the sun, he ascribed the explanation of eclipses to Anaxagoras. 117 Eudemus, to all appearances, shared this view. Inter- estingly, in Hippolytus, who in the case of Anaxagoras employs a reliable do- xographical source, we find the formula pro¯tos heurete¯s, 118 which is frequently attested in the astronomical division of the Physiko¯n doxai. 119 It is very likely that this time it also derives from Theophrastus. This makes it still more plaus- ible that Eudemus, too, mentioned only Anaxagoras; it would have been strange if the views of the two Peripatetics had diverged on this point. Proclus’ commentary on Timaeus contains still another piece of Eudemus’ evidence on the position of both luminaries in Anaxagoras’ system. Comment- ing on the order of planets in Plato – the moon, the sun, Venus, Mercury ( Tim. 38d) – Proclus dwells in detail on a later arrangement (shared by Ptolemy), which placed the sun after Mercury. He concludes with the following note: ô d^ oÑn Plátwn eı~ t3n poll3n koinwnían kaì t3n ômofu4 párodon @pò t4~ aÿt4~ aıtía~ 1líou kaì sel2nh~ próodon aÿtõn !~ sunhmménhn paradédwke. kaì oÿdè taúth~ 7rxen aÿtò~ t4~ ûpoqésew~, @ll^ ^Anaxagóra~ toñto prõto~ ûpélaben, !~ îs- tórhsen EÚdhmo~. At any rate, as Plato saw that there is a lot of common (between the sun and the moon) and that the passage of the sun and the moon is of a similar kind because of the same reason, he also handed down to us their progression into the cosmos as tied together. Meanwhile, it was not Plato who came up with this hypothesis – the first to conceive it was Anaxagoras, as Eudemus reports (fr. 147). It seems to follow from this rather ambiguous passage that Eudemus did not write on the order of planets in Plato, but rather on the close relation between the sun and the moon in Anaxagoras, which he regarded as a certain inno- vation. 120 According to Hippolytus, Anaxagoras believed the moon to be closer to the earth than the sun (59 A 42.7). It remains unclear, however, whether this was his discovery or rather whether Eudemus could consider it a discovery at 115 See also Empedocles (31 B 45). Cf. DK I, 243n.; Heath. Aristarchus, 75f.; Wöhrle, op. cit., 245. 116 Kahn, op. cit., 105 n. 22; Burkert. L & S, 307 n. 40. Doxographical reports on Parme- nides’ moon are contradictory: now it has a fiery nature, now it is lit by the sun ( Dox., 335b 20, 356b 3, 357a 6, 358b 20 = 28 A 37, 42). The fragment on heavenly bodies (B 10) also allows many conflicting readings. 117 Dox., 360b 14f., 23f. (= fr. 227e FHSG), 562.19f. 118 Dox., 562.26 = 59 A 42: o0to~ @førise prõto~ tà perì tà~ ëkleíyei~ kaì fwtismoú~ (sc. t4~ sel2nh~). 119 See above, 161. 120 Heath. Aristarchus, 85; Taylor, A. E. A commentary on Plato’s Timaeus, Oxford 1928, 123. 4. Anaxagoras. The Pythagoreans 257 all. The same order is found in Empedocles (31A 61), who hardly followed An- axagoras here. 121 A further question arises: how does this evidence agree with the fact that Eudemus ascribes to the Pythagoreans the discovery of the ‘cor- rect’ order of heavenly bodies, the one starting with the moon and sun (fr. 146)? Does he mean the Pythagoreans who were a generation younger than Anaxa- goras – Philolaus, for instance? 122 If this is so, and if Eudemus indeed ignored Empedocles, his words may be understood to mean that, while Anaxagoras cor- rectly placed the two luminaries, the Pythagoreans discovered the true arrange- ment of all the heavenly bodies: the moon, the sun, the five planets, and the fixed stars. There is nothing uncommon in dividing a discovery into two parts: according to the History of Geometry, Hippocrates is the first to correctly ap- proach the problem of doubling the cube, while Archytas is the first to solve it. And still, this version implies too many reservations and does not agree very well with what we know of the development of astronomy in the fifth century. There is another possibility. Eudemus’ words on the close relation between the sun and the moon may refer not to the fact that they are closer to the earth than the other planets, 123 but to Anaxagoras’ explanation of eclipses. Proclus must have quoted Eudemus at second hand or from memory; he seems not to know about Eudemus’ testimony that it was the Pythagoreans who introduced the right order of planets, and so takes Anaxagoras’ explanation of eclipses as the introduction of this right order. Such an interpretation allows us to consider Eudemus’ testimonies on Anaxagoras and on the Pythagoreans separately and drops the question of Empedocles’ priority. The astronomy of the fourth century accepted the following order of the heavenly bodies: the moon, the sun, Venus, Mercury, Mars, Jupiter, Saturn. 124 First, this order is attested in Plato, 125 who could have borrowed it from his Py- thagorean friends. But Eudemus obviously had in mind not the Pythagoreans of Plato’s time (e.g., Archytas), but either Philolaus or his precursors. That Phi- lolaus did accept this order is beyond doubt, 126 but was it him Eudemus meant 121 Aristotle ( Met. 984a 11f.) and Theophrastus (fr. 227a FHSG) considered Anaxago- ras to have been older than Empedocles, yet Aristotle added that he was “later in his philosophical activity” (see above, 155 n. 153). 122 As Burkert suggested ( L & S, 313). 123 No evidence on the position of planets in Anaxagoras has survived; it is said, how- ever, that comets appear due to planets’ collisions with each other (59A 1.9, 81). See Burkert. L & S, 311. It cannot be excluded that he placed planets closer to the earth than the moon. Boll, F. Hebdomas, RE 7 (1912) 2566, pointed out that Proclus speaks of the close relation between the sun and the moon, not about the order of the heavenly bodies on the whole. 124 Boll. Hebdomas; Burkert. L & S, 300 n. 7. It relies on the periods of their revolution around the earth: the moon completes its revolution in 29½ days, the sun and the inner planets in a year, etc. 125 Res. 616d–617b; Tim. 38c–d, see also [Pl.] Epin. 987b–d. 126 Aët. II,7.7 = 44 A 16: stars, the five planets, the sun, the moon. Though the do- Chapter 7: The history of astronomy 258 to be the pro¯tos heurete¯s? If so, why did he refer to anonymous Pythagoreans rather than to Philolaus? An answer to this could be prompted by Aristotle’s ac- count of Philolaus’ astronomy: he never calls the latter by name, referring in- stead to the ‘Pythagoreans’ in general. 127 But Theophrastus and Meno (44 A 16–23, 27) had given up this manner of reference, and nothing suggests that Eudemus followed it. Aristotle, while criticizing the ‘Pythagorean’ system, put Download 1.41 Mb. Do'stlaringiz bilan baham: |
Ma'lumotlar bazasi mualliflik huquqi bilan himoyalangan ©fayllar.org 2024
ma'muriyatiga murojaat qiling
ma'muriyatiga murojaat qiling