Leonid Zhmud The Origin of the History of Science in Classical Antiquity
Download 1.41 Mb. Pdf ko'rish
|
The Origin of the History of Science in
floruit
(Jacoby, F. Apollodors Chronik, Berlin 1902, 231, 261f., 278f). The reconstructed date of Oenopides’ birth ca. 484 agrees perfectly with Eudemus’ evidence (see above, 260 n. 133). 151 Burkert. L & S, 314 n. 79; Franciosi, op. cit., 96f. 152 kaì prõto~ tõn ˆEll2nwn EÚdoxo~ ô Knídio~, !~ EÚdhmó~ te ën tŒ deutérœ t4~ @strologik4~ îstoría~ @pemnhmóneuse … (fr. 148). Chapter 7: The history of astronomy 264 text on Ptolemy contains one more excerpt likely to go back to a chronologi- cally arranged history of astronomy: “After Oenopides, Eudoxus won consider- able fame in astronomy.” 153 A notion of Oenopides’ methods in mathematical astronomy can be gained from constructions mentioned in the History of Geometry: how to draw a per- pendicular to a given straight line from a point outside it (I, 12), how to con- struct a rectilinear angle equal to a given rectilinear angle (I, 23), and how to in- scribe a regular pentadecagon in a circle (IV, 16). 154 The elementary character of the first two constructions is obviously at variance with the level of problems that occupied Hippocrates a generation later; usually this was explained by claiming that Oenopides was the first person who attempted to limit geometri- cal construction to the use of ruler and compass. 155 Meanwhile, since Oeno- pides himself considered problem I, 12 to be useful for astronomy and the same is said of problem IV, 16, it seems more natural to explain these constructions by the astronomical context of his work. The expression katà gnømona, used by Oenopides to refer to the perpendicular (I, 12), “since the gnomon stands at a right angle to the horizon”, suggests that his work treated astronomical instru- ments as well. 156 Oenopides, then, might have been the first to attempt to give an astronomical treatise the shape that, though familiar to us from Autolycus’ and Euclid’s works on spherical geometry, must have appeared much earlier. 157 We can surmise, accordingly, that his work, first, incorporated geometrical no- tions of the structure of the universe developed by the Greeks from Anaxi- mander to Anaxagoras and, second, expounded them in conformity with the requirements of the deductive geometry of the mid-fifth century, removing them from the cosmological context to which they belonged in the works of physicists. 158 Interestingly, Neugebauer in his History of Ancient Mathematical Astron- omy, touching on Oenopides’ calendar period, 159 remains silent on other prob- lems that occupied Oenopides, though they proved to be of much greater im- portance for mathematical astronomy. The first of these problems is that of 153 metà dè tòn Oınopídhn, EÚdoxo~ ëpì @strologí+ dóxan 8negken oÿ mikrán (further follows the synchronization of Eudoxus with Plato and Ctesias of Cnidus). Cf.: metà dè toñton Mámerko~ … ëpì gewmetrí+ dóxan … labónto~ (Procl. In Eucl., 65.12f. = Eud. fr. 133). 154 Eud. fr. 138; Procl. In Eucl., 283.7f., 269.8f. 155 Heath. History 1, 175; von Fritz. Oinopides, 2265f. As Knorr. AT, 15f., noted, this claim is groundless. 156 To obtain more or less reliable data, it was important to ensure that the gnomon was perpendicular to the horizontal surface (Szabó, Maula, op. cit., 120). 157 See above, 255 n. 109. 158 The last task was carried out stage by stage (see above, 253 n. 105). 159 Neugebauer. HAMA II, 619. On Oenopides’ calendar cycle, see also Heath. Arist- Download 1.41 Mb. Do'stlaringiz bilan baham: |
Ma'lumotlar bazasi mualliflik huquqi bilan himoyalangan ©fayllar.org 2024
ma'muriyatiga murojaat qiling
ma'muriyatiga murojaat qiling