RT3340X half title 6/22/06 11: 41 am page 1 The Disability


Download 5.02 Mb.
Pdf ko'rish
bet50/61
Sana05.10.2017
Hajmi5.02 Mb.
#17160
1   ...   46   47   48   49   50   51   52   53   ...   61
 Madness Network News Reader. San Francisco: Glide Publications. 

Hogan, M. (2003) “Cover letter: Presidents New Freedom Commission on Mental Health.” Retrieved on June 17, 2005 from 

http://www.mentalhealthcommission.gov/reports/FinalReport/CoverLetter.htm. 

Kessler, R. et al. (2005). Lifetime prevalence and age-of-onset distributions of DSM-IV disorders in the national comorbidity 

survey replication. Archives of General Psychiatry Vol. 62. Retrieved on July 25, 2005 from http://www.archgenpsychiatry.

com.

RT3340X_C028.indd   351



RT3340X_C028.indd   351

7/11/2006   10:18:49 AM

7/11/2006   10:18:49 AM


Bradley Lewis

352


Kirsch, I., and Sapirstein, G. (1998). Listening to Prozac but hearing placebo: A meta-analysis of antidepressant medications. 

Prevention and treatment. Retrieved on July 25, 2005 from http://journals.apa.org/prevention/volume1.

Leifer, R. (1997). Th

  e psychiatric repression of Dr. Th

  omas Szasz: Its social and political signifi cance. Review of Existential 

Psychology and Psychiatry XXIII (1, 2 & 3):85 –107.

Laing, R. (1967). Th

  e politics of experience. New York: Ballantine.

Laing, R..D. (1968) “Th

  e obvious.” In D. Cooper (Ed.). Th

  e dialectics of liberation. Harmondsworth. Penguin.

Latour, B. (1987). Science in action. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. 

Lenzer, J. (2004) “Bush plans to screen whole US population for mental illness.” British Medical Journal. Vol 328. June 19, 2004. 

Retrieved on August 10, 2004 from http://www.bmj.com.

Lewis, B. (2005). “Confi nement.” In G. Albrect (Ed.). Th

  e encyclopedia of disability. Th

  ousand Oaks, CA: Sage Publications.

Lewis, B. (2006). Moving beyond Prozac, DSM, and the new psychiatry: Th

  e birth of postpsychiatry. Ann Arbor: University of 

Michigan Press.

Metzl, J. (2003). Selling sanity through gender: Th

  e psychodynamics of psychotropic advertising. Journal of Medical Humani-

ties 24 (1/2):79–105.

MindFreedom (July 28, 2003). “Original statement by the Fast for Freedom in Mental Health to the American Psychiatric As-

sociation, National Alliance for the Mentally Ill, and the US Offi

  ce of the Surgeon General.” Retrieved on July 10, 2005 

from http://www.mindfreedom.org/mindfreedom/hungerstrike1.shtml#original.

Morrison, L. (2005). Talking back to psychiatry: Th

  e consumer/surivor/ex-patient movement. New York. Routledge.

Mulligan, K. (2002). CMHS budget cuts harm consumer involvement. Psychiatric News 37(6):17. 

Oaks, D. (2002). “From patients to passion: A call for nonviolent revolution in the mental health system. Plenary Address 

Alternatives 2002 Convention. Retrieved on March 3, 2003 from http://www.mindfreedom.org/mindfreedom/confer-

ence.shtml. 

Oaks, D. (2002–2003). “President Bush’s position on people with psychiatric labels.” Mindfreedom Journal (Winter): 4–6.

Oliver, M. (1990). Th

  e politics of disablement: A sociological approach. New York: St. Martin’s Press.

Oliver, M. (1996). Understanding disability: From theory to practice. London: Macmillan.

Packard, E. (1868). Th

  e prisoner’s hidden life, or insane asylums unveiled: As demonstrated by the report of the investigating com-

mittee of the legislature of Illinois. Chicago: Published by the Author, A.B. Case.

Packard, E. (1874). Modern persecutions, or married woman’s liabilities. Hartford, CT: Case, Lockwood and Brainard.

Perlin, M. (2000). Th

  e hidden prejudice: Mental disability on trial. Washington, DC: American Psychological Association. 

President’s New Freedom Commission (2003). “Executive Summary.” Retrieved on June 17, 2005 from http://www.mental-

healthcommission.gov/reports/FinalReport/FullReport.htm.

Pringle, E. (2005). TeenScreen: Th

  e lawsuits begin. CounterPunch. June 13, 2005. Retrieved July 25, 2005 from http://www.

counterpunch.org/pringle06132005.html.

Richman, S. (2004) “Bush’s brave new world.” Th

 e Washington Times. October 17, 2004. Retrieved on July 25, 2005 from http://

www.washingtontimes.com/commentary/20041016-115126-9840r.htm.

Satel, S. (2000). P.C., M.D.: How political correctness is corrupting medicine. New York: Basic Books.

Scheff , T. (1966). Being mentally ill. Chicago: Aldine.

Starfi eld, B. 2000. Is US health really the best in the world? Journal of the American Medical Association 284 (4): 483–-485.

Support Coalition News (May 15, 2002). “Stop the appointment of extremist psychiatrist Sally Satel!” Retrieved on June 15, 

2005 from http://www.mindfreedom.org/mindfreedom/satel_f.shtml.

Szasz, T. (1961). Th

  e myth of mental illness: Foundations of a theory of personal conduct. New York: Hoeber-Harper.

Szasz, T. (1998). “Th

  omas Szasz’s summary statement and manifesto.” Retrieved on July 20, 2005 from http://www.szasz.

com/manifesto.html. 

Th

  omas, P., and Bracken, P. (2004). Critical psychiatry in practice. Advances in Psychiatric Treatment 10:361–370.



Van Tosh, L., and del Vecchio, P. (2000). Consumer-operated and self-help programs: A technical report. Rockville, MD: U.S. 

Center for Mental Health Services. 

Whitaker, R. (2002). Mad in America: Bad science, bad medicine, and the enduring mistreatment of the mentally ill. Cambridge, 

MA: Perseus Publishing.

“Windows into madness” (2002). Adbusters (10) 3. 

Zinnman, S., Howie the Harp, and Budd, S. (Eds.) (1987). Reaching across: Mental health clients helping each other. Sacramento, 

CA: California Network of Mental Health Clients. 

RT3340X_C028.indd   352

RT3340X_C028.indd   352

7/11/2006   10:18:49 AM

7/11/2006   10:18:49 AM


Part VI

Disability and Culture

RT3340X_P006.indd   353

RT3340X_P006.indd   353

7/11/2006   10:34:52 AM

7/11/2006   10:34:52 AM


RT3340X_P006.indd   354

RT3340X_P006.indd   354

7/11/2006   10:34:55 AM

7/11/2006   10:34:55 AM



355

29

Toward a Poetics of Vision, Space, and the Body



Sign Language and Literary Theory

1

H-Dirksen L. Bauman



Suppose that we had no voice or tongue, and wanted to communicate with one another, should we not, 

like the deaf . . . make signs with the hands and head and the rest of the body?

—Plato Th

 e Cratylus (212)

An exchange between literary theory and sign languages is long overdue. Centuries overdue: for as 

early as Plato’s Cratylus, Western “hearing” intellectuals have been aware of the manual languages of 

Deaf



communities, but twenty-fi ve centuries since Plato, we remain largely ignorant that our concepts 



of language and literature have evolved within a false dualism of speech and writing. Only as recently 

as William Stokoe’s linguistic research in the 1960s, have we realized that Sign

3

 is an “offi



  cial” human 

language with the capacity to generate a nearly infi nite number of propositions from a vast lexicon. 

Yet, while linguists have been exploring this revolution in language, literary critics remain largely 

unaware that Sign is a natural linguistic mode capable of producing a body of literature.

4

 Th


 is body 

of literature is, rather, a literature of the body that transforms the linear model of speech and writing 

into an open linguistic fi eld of vision, time, space, and the body.

As Sign literature emerges in the late twentieth century, we can only wonder how its absence has 

helped to shape our ideas about language, literature, and the world. We must wonder if Sign’s absence 

has lead to hidden limits and desires in our relationship to language. One could, perhaps, argue that 

speech and writing have been searching for their visual/spatial counterpart since Simonides of Keos’ 

formulation that “poetry is speaking painting” while “painting is mute poetry,” and extending through, 

among others, Horace’s dictum ut pictura poesis, centuries of religious “pattern poetry,”

5

 Blake’s illustra-



tions, Stein’s cubism, Pound’s ideograms, Olson’s hieroglyphics, concrete poetry, performance poetry, 

ethnopoetics, video-texts, and virtual texts. Th

  ese experiments have, in their various ways, sought to 

imbue speech and writing with the visual and spatial dimensions of images and the body. Have these 

experiments emerged out of a phantom-limb phenomenon where writers have sensed language’s 

severed visual-spatial mode and went groping aft er it?

6

 If the Deaf poet had been mythologized as 



the blind poet has been, would literature have developed diff erently? Would the map which draws the 

historical relation between visual and literary arts have to be redrawn? What sorts of genres would 

have emerged? Would our metaphysical heritage have been diff erent if we were not only the speaking 

but also the “signing animal”?

While these questions are beyond the scope of the present essay, they lead toward its general 

purpose: to show that what many scholars would consider the marginal literary practices (if you can 

even call them “literary”) of “disabled” persons is, on the contrary, of central importance to any one, 

hearing or Deaf, who is interested in the relations of language and literature to culture, identity, and 

being. In order to recognize Sign as a medium for literature, we must open an exchange between Sign 

and theory by exploring ways that theory enhances our understanding of Sign and ways that Sign 

RT3340X_C029.indd   355

RT3340X_C029.indd   355

7/11/2006   10:16:22 AM

7/11/2006   10:16:22 AM



H-Dirksen L. Bauman

356


enhances—and challenges—our understanding of theory and literature. Th

  is opening exchange will 

ask numerous questions that will gesture toward a more in-depth study of Sign literature.

Th

  e following dialogue between Sign and theory is more like a conference call between Sign and 



interconnected and contradictory areas of criticism: deconstruction, cultural studies (at the intersec-

tion of feminism/postcolonialism/multiculturalism), semiotics, and phenomenology. Rather than 

applying a monolithic paradigm, I hope to assemble a collection of perspectives that will off er the 

best vantage points from which to explore a nonwritten, spatial form of literature. Th

 is eclectic ap-

proach is especially important as the small body of criticism of Sign literature remains rooted in 

one-dimensional approaches. Th

  e formalist analyses of Clayton Valli and Edward Klima and Ursula 

Bellugi and the semiotic approaches of Jim Cohn and Heidi Rose are much needed contributions 

to their fi eld, but are unable to place Sign literature in its proper historical, political, metaphysical 

perspective—which is the goal of this present study. My intent, though, is ultimately not to feed Sign 

poems through a convoluted critical machine to produce insightful “readings” or rather, “viewings”; 

instead, one hopes these concepts and connections will eventually develop dialogically with Sign 

poetic practices themselves.

Deconstruction and Deafness: Phonocentrism, Audism, and Sign Language

Th

  e exchange between theory and Sign should open, appropriately, with Jacques Derrida, for it is he 



who has brought the importance of nonphonetic linguistic modalities to the forefront of twentieth-

century thought by severing the “natural” connection between the voice and language. Th

 e voice, 

Derrida believes, is more than a means of communicating—it is the source for Western ideas of 

truth, being, and presence. Th

  e system of “hearing-oneself-speak,” Derrida contends, “has necessarily 

dominated the history of the world during an entire epoch, and has even produced the idea of the 

world, the idea of world-origin” (8). Th

  is constitutive role of the voice results from the self-presence 

created by hearing-oneself-speak. One’s own voice is completely interior, fully present to the speaker; 

it is the source of self-identity, of self-presence. Meaning constituted within this full-presence then 

becomes the standard for notions of identity, precipitating a metaphysics based on the full-presence 

of self, meaning, and identity. Th

  e privileging of the voice, which Derrida calls “phonocentrism,” is 

the linguistic phenomenon that leads toward “logocentrism,” the Western metaphysical orientation 

which perceives meaning to be anchored by the self-presence of identity. Against this tradition, Der-

rida recognizes that the voice has no natural primacy over nonphonetic forms of language and that 

the metaphysics of presence is infused with the free-play and undecidability of language. Seeking to 

deconstruct phonocentric metaphysics, Derrida explores nonphonetic forms of language—hieroglyph-

ics, ideograms, algebraic notations, and nonlinear writing. His explorations lead beyond phonocentric 

linguistics toward “grammatology,” a science of writing and textuality.

When seen through deconstructive lenses, Sign dilates its sphere of infl uence from the socio-

political site of the Deaf community to the entire history of Western “hearing” metaphysics. With 

its deconstruction of the voice-centered tradition, grammatology, one might say, initiates a “Deaf 

philosophy”—if it weren’t for the fact that Derrida fails to engage theoretical issues of deafness or 

signing to any signifi cant degree. Th

  e exchange between Sign and deconstruction, then, recognizes the 

metaphysical implications of Sign while Sign, in turn, extends the project of deconstruction beyond 

its own limitations drawn by the exclusion of Sign and Deaf history.

Th

  e theoretical signifi cance of “deafness,” in this sense, takes on new historical and metaphysical 



importance that pathologized “deafness” cannot. If nonphonetic writing interrupts the primacy of 

the voice, deafness signifi es the consummate moment of disruption. Deafness exiles the voice from 

the body, from meaning, from being; it sabotages its interiority from within, corrupting the system 

which has produced the “hearing” idea of the world. Deafness, then, occupies a consummate moment 

in the deconstruction of Western ontology. Further, deafness does more than disrupt the system of 

“hearing-oneself-speak”; it creates an embodied linguistic system which, unlike speech, is not fully 

RT3340X_C029.indd   356

RT3340X_C029.indd   356

7/11/2006   10:16:27 AM

7/11/2006   10:16:27 AM



357

Toward a Poetics of Vision, Space, and the Body

present to itself. Signers, unless gazing into the mirror, do not fully see themselves signify. While they 

may see their hands, they cannot see their own face perform much of Sign’s grammatical nuances. 

Th

  e eye, unlike the ear in the system of “hearing-oneself-speak,” can only partially “see-oneself-sign.” 



Th

  ere is always a trace of nonpresence in the system of signing.

One wonders, then, if Derrida had engaged the theoretical implications of deafness and Sign further

might he have expanded the term “Sign” as he did “Writing” to signify diff erance, Derrida’s neologism 

that cannot be spoken but only seen, signifying that phonetic writing is not simply a copy of speech. At 

this point, we can only begin to conjecture what sort of diff erent philosophical resonance would occur 

by re-reading deconstruction with regards to Sign in the place of—or in addition to—writing.

While Derrida does not engage the theoretical implications of deafness or Sign in any depth, he 

does entertain Rousseau’s contradictory relation to the language of gesture, which Rousseau attributes 

to Deaf persons on occasion. Early in the Essay on the Origin of Human Languages when Rousseau 

imagines that a society could develop arts, commerce, government—all without recourse to speech. 

Aft er all, Rousseau writes, “Th

  e mutes of great nobles understand each other and understand every-

thing that is said to them by means of signs, just as well as one can understand anything said in dis-

course” (Essay 9). Th

  is observation leads Rousseau to muse that “the art of communicating our ideas 

depends less upon the organs we use in such communication than it does upon a power proper to 

man, according to which he uses his organs in this way, and which, if he lacked these, would lead him 

to use others to the same end” (10). Derrida seizes on this nonphonocentric moment in Rousseau to 

destabilize the primacy of the voice in Western philosophy. “It is once again the power of substituting 

one organ for another,” Derrida writes, “of articulating space and time, sign and voice, hand and spirit, 

it is this faculty of supplementarity which is the true origin—or nonorigin—of languages” (241). As 

the condition leading toward the supplement, deafness could be read, ironically, as that which makes 

the origin of language possible. Deafness summonses up the visual-spatial dimension of language to 

supplant the voice from within. It sets diff erance in motion.

Th

  is inversion of deafness—from linguistic isolation to the precondition of language itself—has 



political implications for the Deaf community’s diffi

  cult task of depathologizing Deaf identity within 

the culture of academia. Aft er considering deafness in relation to deconstruction, one may begin to 

see the Deaf community—not as a group defi ned by its pathological relation to language—but rather 

as an example of a culture fl ourishing beyond the reaches of logocentrism. Th

  e possibility of such a 

community raises questions. Is resisting phonocentrism tantamount to resisting logocentrism? What 

are the phenomenological diff erences between “being-in-the deaf-world” and “being-in-the-hearing-

world”? Are Deaf persons—over ninety percent of whom are born in hearing families—really out of 

reach of logocentrism? By raising issues surrounding Sign to the metaphysical level, could the argument 

for a Deaf cultural identity be expanded beyond the anthropological and socio-linguistic identifi ca-

tions of distinctly “Deaf ”  cultural acts—such as Deaf folklore, jokes, attention getting strategies, and 

social organizations—to encompass a deeper level: a level that Sign and “not-hearing-oneself-speak” 

creates outside of hearing-dominated metaphysics?

Given the relevance of these questions to grammatology, it is surprising that Derrida never engages 

signing and deafness as theoretically and historically signifi cant issues.

7

 When he does mention deaf-



ness it is through the “voices” of others: Hegel, Leibniz, Rousseau, and Saussure. Making others speak 

about deafness is a strange ventriloquism which demonstrates that Derrida is aware, obviously, of 

Sign and Deaf communities. One may link this critical oversight as being symptomatic of not really 

seeing Deaf people, of tacitly acknowledging their absence from being. If this is so, this audist oversight 

reinscribes the very phonocentrism Derrida sets out to deconstruct. At the very least, one may accuse 

Derrida’s grammatology of suff ering from an undertheorized sociopolitical site because he neglects 

Deaf history. While he considers logocentrism to be “the most original and powerful ethnocentrism,” 

(3) he does not follow this statement to its most severe sociopolitical manifestation: audism.

Audism is the most extreme deployment of phonocentrism ranging from incarcerating Deaf persons 

in mental institutions, to eugenics movements (one sponsored by Alexander Graham Bell in America, 

another currently practiced in China), to the oppression of sign language in the  education of Deaf 

RT3340X_C029.indd   357

RT3340X_C029.indd   357

7/11/2006   10:16:27 AM

7/11/2006   10:16:27 AM


H-Dirksen L. Bauman

358


persons. Many Deaf adults today tell of their violent experiences growing up in oralist schools—their 

hands slapped or tied behind their backs if they were caught signing.

8

 Further, early Deaf schools of-



fered a collection of subjugated bodies on which doctors could develop the science of otology. Acids, 

needles, and hammers all violated the ears and skulls of Deaf children so that they could be returned 

to “normal.”

9

While he could have made many relevant connections between phonocentrism and oralist edu-



cational practices, Derrida instead labels the condemnation of Leibniz’s desire for a nonphonetic, 

universal script as “the most energetic eighteenth-century reaction organizing the defense of pho-

nologism and of logocentric metaphysics” (99). I propose, instead, that the history of deaf education, 

as it is marked by violent oppression of sign and the subjugation of Deaf persons, is a more “energetic 

reaction” to phonocentrism. It is where phonocentrism meets social and educational policy. Indeed, 

nowhere will one fi nd a more vehement declaration of voice-as-presence than by reading the words 

of oralist educators. Consider, for example, the following declaration from the father of deaf educa-

tion in German-speaking lands:

Th

  e breath of life resides in the voice. . . . Th



  e voice is a living emanation of that spirit that God breathed 

into man when he created him a living soul . . . What stupidity we fi nd in most of these unfortunate 

deaf . . . How  little  they  diff er from animals. (Lane, 107)

Th

  is all too common association between Deaf persons and animals off ers arguably the most vivid 



illustration of Derrida’s central connection between voice and human presence. As Douglas Baynton, 

Harlan Lane, and others have shown, Deaf identity has been publicly constructed through metaphorics 

of animality, darkness, imprisonment, and isolation, resulting in a relay of hierarchized binary opposi-

tions which divide along the axis of absence and presence: animal/human; prisoner/property owner; 

foreigner/citizen; darkness/light; normality/pathology. Just as the Deaf voice is exiled from its own 

body, Deaf persons have been exiled from the phonocentric body-politic.


Download 5.02 Mb.

Do'stlaringiz bilan baham:
1   ...   46   47   48   49   50   51   52   53   ...   61




Ma'lumotlar bazasi mualliflik huquqi bilan himoyalangan ©fayllar.org 2024
ma'muriyatiga murojaat qiling