Al-Ghaza¯lı¯’s Philosophical


Download 4.03 Mb.
Pdf ko'rish
bet1/55
Sana07.11.2017
Hajmi4.03 Mb.
#19584
  1   2   3   4   5   6   7   8   9   ...   55

 Al-Ghaza¯lı¯’s Philosophical 

Theology 



This page intentionally left blank 

 Al-Ghaza¯lı¯’s 

Philosophical 

Theology 

 Fr ank  Griffel 

2009


 Oxford University Press, Inc., publishes works that further 

 Oxford University’s objective of excellence 

 in research, scholarship, and education. 

 Oxford 


New  York 

 Auckland  Cape Town  Dar es Salaam  Hong Kong  Karachi 

 

Kuala 


Lumpur Madrid Melbourne Mexico 

City Nairobi 

 

New 


Delhi Shanghai Taipei Toronto 

 With  offi ces in 

 

Argentina Austria Brazil Chile Czech 



Republic France Greece 

 

Guatemala Hungary Italy Japan Poland Portugal Singapore 



 

South 


Korea Switzerland Thailand Turkey Ukraine Vietnam 

 Copyright © 2009 by Frank Griffel 

   Published by Oxford University Press, Inc. 

 198 Madison Avenue, New York, New York 10016 

 www.oup.com 

 Oxford is a registered trademark of Oxford University Press 

 All rights reserved. No part of this publication may be reproduced, 

 stored in a retrieval system, or transmitted, in any form or by any means, 

 electronic, mechanical, photocopying, recording, or otherwise, 

 without the prior permission of Oxford University Press. 

 Library of Congress Cataloging-in-Publication Data 

 Griffel, Frank, 1965– 

 Al-Ghazali’s philosophical theology / Frank Griffel. 

  

p. 



cm. 

 Includes bibliographical references and index. 

 ISBN  978-0-19-533162-2 

 

1. Ghazzali, 1058–1111.  2. Islamic cosmology.  3. Philosophy, Islamic. 



 I.  Title. 

 B753.G34G75 

2009 

 

181'.5—dc22   2008030813 



 

9 8 7 6 5 4 3 2 1 

 Printed in the United States of America 

 on acid-free paper 



 per Magda Lena e Tanya 

 La gloria di colui che tutto move 

 per l’universo penetra, e risplende 

 in una parte più e meno altrove. 

 —Dante,   Paradiso ,  1.1–3 

This page intentionally left blank 

 Contents 

 Timetable ,  xi

 Introduction ,  3

  1.   A Life between Public and Private Instruction: Al-Ghaza¯lı¯’s 

Biography ,  19

 The Main Sources for al-Ghaza¯lı¯’s Biography , 21

 Al-Ghaza¯lı¯’s Date of Birth: Around 448/1056 , 23

 Al-Ghaza¯lı¯’s Early Years and His Education , 25

 Becoming a Famous Jurist and Theologian , 31

 Leaving Baghdad, Traveling in Syria and the Hijaz, 

and Returning to Khorasan , 40

 The Ideal of a Secluded Life—His Last Years 

in Khorasan , 49

 2.   Al-Ghaza¯lı¯’s Most Infl uential Students and Early 

Followers ,  61

 Abu


¯ Bakr ibn al- ¶Arabı¯ (d. 543/1148) , 62

 Ibn  al- ¶Arabı¯’s First Report of His Meeting 

with al-Ghaza¯lı¯ ,  65

 Ibn  al- ¶Arabı¯’s Second Report of His Meeting 

with al-Ghaza¯lı¯ ,  66

 As ¶ad al-Mayhanı¯ (d. 523/1130 or 527/1132–33) , 71

 Mu .hammad ibn Ya.hya¯ al-Janzı¯ (d. 549/1154) , 74

 Ibn  Tu


¯mart (d. 524/1130) , 77

 ¶Ayn al-Qud.a¯t al-Hamadha¯nı¯ (d. 525/1131) , 81

 The Anonymous Author of  The Lion and the Diver  

al-Asad wa-l-ghawwa¯s. ) ,  87



v i i i   c on t e n t s

   3.   Al-Ghaza¯lı¯ on the Role of  falsafa  in Islam , 97

 The Refutation of the  fala¯sifa  in the  Incoherence   ( Taha¯fut ) ,  98

 Al-Ghaza¯lı¯’s  fatwa¯  against Three Teachings of the  fala¯sifa  ,  101

 Unbelief and Apostasy , 103

  The Decisive Criterion   ( Fays.al al-tafriqa ) ,  105

  4.   The Reconciliation of Reason and Revelation through 

the “Rule of Interpretation” ( Qa¯nu



¯n al-ta 7wı¯l ) ,  111

 Three Different Types of Passages in Revelation , 115

 A Dispute about al-Ghaza¯lı¯’s Approach: Ibn Ghayla¯n versus 

Fakhr al-Dı¯n al-Ra¯zı¯ ,  116

 Demonstrative Knowledge ( burha¯n ) and Its Opposite: Emulation 

of Authorities ( taqlı¯d  ) ,  120

   5.   Cosmology in Early Islam: Developments That Led to al-Ghaza¯lı¯’s 

 Incoherence of the Philosophers  ,  123

 Ash ¶arite Occasionalism in the Generations before al-Ghaza¯lı¯ ,  124

 Secondary Causes in Ash ¶arite Theology , 128

 The   fala¯sifa ’s View of Creation by Means of Secondary Causality , 133

 The   fala¯sifa ’s View That This World Is Necessary , 141

 Al-Ghaza¯lı¯’s Treatment of Causality in MS London, Or. 3126 , 143

 6.   The Seventeenth Discussion of  The Incoherence of the Philosophers  ,  147

 The First Position: Observation Does Not Establish 

Causal Connections , 150

 The First Approach of the Second Position: How the Natural 

Sciences Are Possible Even in an Occasionalist Universe , 153

 The Second Approach of the Second Position: An Immanent 

Explanation of Miracles , 156

 Overcoming Occasionalism: The Third Position , 157

 Julian Obermann’s “Subjectivist” Interpretation of the 

Seventeenth Discussion , 160

 Al-Ghaza¯lı¯’s Critique of Avicenna’s Conception of the 

Modalities ,  162

 The Different Conceptions of the Modalities in  falsafa  

and  kala¯m  ,  167

 What Does al-Ghaza¯lı¯ Mean When He Claims That Causal 

Connections Are Not Necessary? , 172

   7.   Knowledge of Causal Connection Is Necessary , 175

 The Dispute over al-Ghaza¯lı¯’s Cosmology , 179

 Five Conditions for Cosmological Explanations 

in the  Incoherence  ,  183

 Determination by an Unchanging Divine Foreknowledge , 187

 Divine Foreknowledge in the  Revival of Religious Sciences  ,  190

 Prophetical Miracles and the Unchanging Nature 

of God’s Habit , 194

 Necessary Knowledge in an Occasionalist Universe , 201



  c on t e n t s  

i x


 Concomitant Events and Rational Judgments , 204

 Experience  ( tajriba ) in Avicenna and in al-Ghaza¯lı¯ ,  208

  8. Causes and Effects in  The Revival of the Religious Sciences  ,  215

 The Creation of Human Acts , 216

 The Conditional Dependence of God’s Actions , 222

 The Conditions of a Creation That Is the Best of All Possible 

Creations ,  225

 The Necessity of the Conditions in God’s Creation , 231

 9. Cosmology in Works Written after  The Revival  ,  235

 God’s Creation as an Apparatus: The Simile of the Water 

Clock ,  236

 Cosmology in  The Highest Goal in Explaining the Beautiful 



Names of God  ,  242

  The Niche of Lights : The Philosophers’ God as the First 

Created Being , 245

 The Cosmology of the “Fourth Group” in the Veil Section of 

 The Niche of Lights  ,  253

 An  Isma¯ ¶ı¯lite Infl uence on the Cosmology in the Veil Section? , 260

 Final Doubts about Cosmology:  Restraining the Ordinary People  

Ilja¯m al- awa¯mm ) ,  265

 Conclusion ,  275

 Notes ,  287

 Bibliography ,  361

   General  Index ,  395

Index of Works by al-Ghaza¯lı¯, 403

Index of Manuscripts, 405

Index of Verses in the Qur’an, 407


This page intentionally left blank 

 

 Timetable 

 445/1053 

 The persecution of Ash ¶arites in Khorasan 

(in north-east Iran) begins. Al-Juwaynı¯ 

emigrates to the Hijaz; Abu

¯ l-Qa¯sim 

al-Qushayrı¯ is incarcerated in Nishapur, 

the capital of Khorasan. 

 Circa  448/1056 

 Al-Ghaza¯lı¯ is born in T.a¯bara¯n, one of 

two major towns in the district of T.u¯s 

in northeast Iran. 

 455/1063 

 The death of Sultan Toghril-Bey ends the 

threat of persecution for the Ash ¶arites 

in Khorasan. Alp Arslan becomes his 

successor; his vizier Niz.a¯m al-Mulk 

supports Ash ¶arism. Al-Juwaynı¯ returns 

to Nishapur and becomes head teacher at 

the Niz.a¯miyya madrasa. 

 Circa 461/1069 

 At age thirteen, al-Ghaza¯lı¯ begins his 

“plunge into the sea of religious sciences.” 

After studying with local teachers in 

T.u¯s, he enters the Niz.a¯miyya madrasa in 

Nishapur and studies with al-Juwaynı¯. 

 465/1072 

 Alp Arslan is assassinated; his son 

Maliksha¯h becomes sultan; Niz.a¯m al-

Mulk becomes an even more powerful 

vizier. According to a statement in one of 

al-Ghaza¯lı¯ letters, it was at this time that 

he joins the service of Maliksha¯h. 



x i i   t im e table

 Circa  473/1080 

 Al-Ghaza¯lı¯ composes his fi rst book,  The Sifted   ( al-

Mankhu¯l ). 

 478/1085 

 Al-Juwaynı¯ dies in Nishapur. Now or sometime 

earlier, al-Ghaza¯lı¯ joins the entourage ( mu askar )  of 

Niz.a¯m al-Mulk. He spends most of his time in the 

Seljuq capital Isfahan. 

 Juma¯da I 484 / July 1091   Al-Ghaza¯lı¯ arrives in Baghdad from Isfahan to take 

his post as head teacher of the Niz.a¯miyya madrasa. 

 Ramad.a¯n 485 /  

Assassination  of  Niz.a¯m al-Mulk on the road be-

October 1092 

 tween Isfahan and Baghdad. 

 Shawwa¯l 485 /  

Death of Maliksha¯h in Baghdad. His succession is

November 1092 

 contested between the supporters of his two minor 

sons Berk-Yaruq and Ma.hmu¯d, who have different 

mothers. Al-Ghaza¯lı¯ is involved in the negotiations 

with Terken Kha¯tu

¯n, a Qipchak princess and the 

mother of Ma.hmu¯d, about the appointment of her 

son as sultan. 

 Mu.harram 487 /  

After the death of Ma.hmu¯d and his mother, Terken

February 1094 

 Kha¯tu


¯n, Berk-Yaruq is declared Sultan of the Seljuq 

Empire. A day after his appointment, the caliph al-

Muqtadı¯ dies in Baghdad. His fi fteen-year-old son, 

al-Mustaz.hir (d. 512/1118), becomes his successor. 

 Mu.harram 488 /  

Al-Ghaza¯lı¯ completes work on The Incoherence of the

January 1095 

  Philosophers.  

 Dhu

¯ l-Qa ¶da 488 /  



Al-Ghaza¯lı¯ suddenly gives up his post at the Niz.-

November 1095 

 a¯miyya madrasa, departs from Baghdad, and travels 

to Damascus. 

 Summer 489 / 1096 

 Al-Ghaza¯lı¯ travels from Damascus to Jerusalem. 

 Dhu

¯ l-Qa ¶da 489 /  



He visits Hebron and vows at the grave of Abraham

October– 

no longer to serve state authorities. From Hebron,

November 1096 

 he joins the pilgrimage caravan to Mecca. 

 Dhu


¯ l-.hijja 489 /  

Pilgrimage to Mecca, later to Medina.

November– 

December 1096 

  

 Mu.harram 490 /  



Al-Ghaza¯lı¯ returns to Damascus. His host, Abu

¯ 

January 1097 



 l-Fat .h Nas.r, had just died. Al-Ghaza¯lı¯ stays only a few 

months and embarks on his return to Baghdad. 

 Juma¯da II 490 /  

Al-Ghaza¯lı¯ arrives in Baghdad. He reads from his

May–June 1097 

  Revival of the Religious Sciences.  



  t im e table  

x i i i


 490/1097 

 Berk-Yaruq appoints his half brother Sanjar as gov-

ernor ( malik ) of Khorasan. He reigns in Khorasan 

until a few years before his death in 552/1157. 

 Fall of 490 / 1097 

 Al-Ghaza¯lı¯ leaves Baghdad for Khorasan. 

 Dhu

¯ l-.hijja 490 /  



Al-Ghaza¯lı¯ arrives in Khorasan. He establishes a

November 1097 

 madrasa and a  kha¯nqa¯h   in  T.a¯bara¯n-T.u¯s where he 

teaches numerous students. 

 

497/1104 



 

Berk-Yaruq agrees to a division of power with 

his half brothers Mu .hammad Tapar and Sanjar. 

Mu .hammad Tapar becomes ruler of northwestern 

Persia, the Jazira, and Syria, while Sanjar remains 

in Khorasan, acknowledging Berk-Yaruk as the su-

preme sultan. 

 498/1105 

 Death of Berk-Yaruq. Mu .hammad Tapar becomes 

the supreme sultan in Isfahan. Sanjar remains his 

governor ( malik ) in Khorasan. 

 Summer 499 / 1106 

 Under pressure from Sanjar and assurances from 

his vizier, Fakhr al-Mulk, al-Ghaza¯lı¯ begins to teach 

at the Niz.a¯miyya madrasa in Nishapur. 

 Mu.harram 500 /  

Isma¯ ¶ı¯lite agents asassinate Fakhr al-Mulk.

September 1106 

  

 around  502/1109 



 Al-Ghaza¯lı¯ is summoned before Sanjar and con-

fronted with accusations of his adversaries. A short 

time later, he composes the Persian mirror for 

princes  Council for Kings   (Nas.ı¯.hat al-mulu¯k  ). 

 Fall of 504 / 1110 

 After the death of al-Kiya¯ 7 al-Harra¯sı¯ in Baghdad, al-

Ghaza¯lı¯ is offered the same position at the Baghdad 

Niz.a¯miyya that he left fi fteen years earlier. He de-

clines in a widely publicized letter. 

 14  Juma¯da II 505 /  

Al-Ghaza¯lı¯ dies in his  

kha¯nqa¯h 

 in T.a¯bara¯n-T.u¯s.

18 December 1111 

   


This page intentionally left blank 

 Al-Ghaza¯lı¯’s Philosophical 

Theology 



This page intentionally left blank 

 Introduction 

 Today people both in the West and in the Muslim world think of 

 Islamic civilization as a phenomenon of the past. We assume that 

like the ancient Egyptian or Roman civilizations, the Islamic civiliza-

tion had a “Golden Age,” a period of prosperity and discovery from 

the second/eighth to the sixth/twelfth centuries that was followed 

by decline and the rise of another, more innovative civilization. This 

later civilization is usually referred to as “the West,” a vague term that 

includes the achievements of Galileo Galilei and Christopher Colum-

bus just as much as the development of the personal computer and 

the Internet search engine. Since the eighteenth century, scholars 

in the West who have examined the reasons for the end of Islam’s 

“Golden Age” often focus on the differing roles of philosophy in 

these two cultures. 

1

  In the West, philosophy and the production of ra-



tional arguments have always been regarded as motors that triggered 

and accelerated the development of new ideas and technologies. It 

was assumed, however, that although in the Islamic world philosophy 

grew tremendously during its Golden Age, later scholars in Muslim 

societies abandoned the study of philosophy and turned their atten-

tion toward religious scholarship. During the nineteenth century, 

Western researchers of Islam developed a by-now well-established 

account of the fate of philosophy in Islam, postulating that Islamic 

civilization became acquainted with the tradition of Greek philosophy 

during the second/eighth and third/ninth centuries, when many 

philosophical works—most important the writings of Aristotle and 

their ancient commentaries—were translated into Arabic. These 

translations triggered the development of a philosophic movement in 

Islam known in Arabic as  falsafa  (from the Greek word  philosophía ). 

This movement was not limited to Muslims, and included Christian, 


4   a l - gh a z a

¯ l 1


¯ ’ s   ph ilosoph ic a l   t h e olo g y

Jewish, and even some pagan authors. It benefi ted from the open-mindedness 

and curiosity about other societies that characterizes the early Islamic period. 

Although  falsafa  developed in Islamic society, it quickly became subject to the 

harsh criticism of a conservative group of Muslims. Still, until the fi fth/elev-

enth century, the philosophical movement in Islam was able to generate signif-

icant support among scholars, literates, and, most important, caliphs and local 

rulers who patronized their works. During these years,  falsafa  and its critics 

existed side-by-side among the numerous intellectual movements of classical 

Islam. According to the traditional understanding, which dominated Western 

Islamic studies through the nineteenth and most of the twentieth centuries, 

philosophy ceased to exist in Islam after the sixth/twelfth century. It was as-

sumed that some of the instigating factors for its disappearance were political, 

such as a lack of patronage from local rulers; some of them economical, such 

as an assumed demise of the city economies after the arrival of nomadic Turks 

in the mid-fi fth/eleventh century; and some of them educational, such as the 

beginning of a state-sponsored system of religious seminaries ( madrasa s)  that 

supposedly favored traditionalist religious scholarship and put obstacles to the 

pursuit of the rational sciences. According to this account, these factors led to 

the demise of rational science and philosophy under Islam. 

 Tjitze J. de Boer’s  History of Philosophy in Islam , published in German in 

1901 and in English two years later, was the fi rst textbook on this subject. It 

ends its presentation—apart from an appendix on the thought of Ibn Khaldu¯n 

(d. 808/1406)—with Averroes (Ibn Rushd), who died in 595/1198. De Boer re-

alized that, after Averroes, there were philosophical teachers and students “by 

hundreds and by thousands.” Yet these were mostly epitomists—that is, au-

thors who only commented on early works without themselves contributing 

original thoughts—he says, and after Averroes, “philosophy was not permitted 

to infl uence general culture or the condition of affairs.” 

2

  In a widely read article 



of 1916, Ignaz Goldziher analyzed the attitude of Muslim theologians toward 

the rationalist sciences. He concluded that although there had always been op-

position to rational science among the theologians of Islam, after the fi fth/

eleventh  century, this opposition manifested itself much more forcefully. In the 

case of philosophical logics, for instance, he concluded that “from this period 

on, the study of logic was more or less decisively considered to be part of the 

category of  haram   (forbidden).” 

3

  In an earlier article, Goldziher had already said 



that with Averroes, the history of philosophy in Islam had come to an end. 

4

  



 When new sources and fresh studies corrected Goldziher’s view that the 

study of logic fell into decay after the fi fth/eleventh century—there was indeed 

a blossoming of logics in the three subsequent centuries—this traditional view 

of the fate of philosophy in Islam did not change. In the 1960s, for instance, 

George Makdisi argued that the main current in Muslim theological thought 

after the fi fth/eleventh century was represented by conservative traditionalists 

such as Ibn Taymiyya (d. 728/1328), who opposed  falsafa . 

5

  In a well-received in-



troductory textbook on Islam, Jonathan Berkey wrote in 2003 that between the 

fi fth/eleventh and ninth/fi fteenth centuries, the rational sciences such as phi-



  in t roduc t ion  

5

losophy and logics tended to become marginalized from what he calls “Sunni 



intellectual mainstream.” 

6

  



 The  infl uential Muslim theologian al-Ghaza¯lı¯ (d. 505/1111) has always played 

a leading role in Western attempts to explain the assumed decline of philoso-

phy in Islam. In his work  The Incoherence of the Philosophers   ( Taha¯fut al-fala¯sifa ), 

al-Ghaza¯lı¯ criticizes twenty teachings of the Muslim philosophers. According 

to al-Ghaza¯lı¯, three of those twenty teachings not only are unproven but also vi-

olate central tenets of Islam that all Muslims have agreed upon. For al-Ghaza¯lı¯, 

these three teachings mark a departure from Islam. These are the views (1) that 

the word has no beginning in the past and is not created in time, (2) that God’s 

knowledge includes only classes of beings (universals) and does not extend to 

individual beings and their circumstances (particulars), and (3) that after death 

the souls of humans will never again return into bodies. In these three cases, 

the teachings of Islam, which are based on revelation, suggest the opposite, 

al-Ghaza¯lı¯ says, and thus overrule the unfounded claims of the Muslim phi-

losophers. Those people who actively propagate these three teachings cannot 

be regarded as Muslims, he says. Rather, they are apostates from Islam and—

 according to a ruling of Islamic law—subject to the death penalty. 

7

  

 The fact that the alleged end of the philosophical tradition in Islam largely 



coincided with al-Ghaza¯lı¯’s condemnation of 487/1095, or happened within 

the next three generations, triggered the suggestion that his verdict contrib-

uted to or even caused the disappearance of philosophy in Islam. Solomon 

Munk, author of the fi rst comprehensive history of Arabic and Islamic phi-

losophy, set the tone of the debate when in 1844, he wrote that with his  In-

coherence ,  al-Ghaza¯lı¯ “struck a blow against philosophy from which it never 

recovered in the Orient.” 

8

  Soon thereafter, Ernest Renan described al-Ghaza¯lı¯ 


Download 4.03 Mb.

Do'stlaringiz bilan baham:
  1   2   3   4   5   6   7   8   9   ...   55




Ma'lumotlar bazasi mualliflik huquqi bilan himoyalangan ©fayllar.org 2024
ma'muriyatiga murojaat qiling