International Relations. A self-Study Guide to Theory
Download 0.79 Mb. Pdf ko'rish
|
International Relations (Theory)
ists. In the second complex, the focus will be more related to how to know
and the methodology of knowing. 44 2.2. Epistemology, ontology and methodology in positivist science 2.2.1. Complex 1 Positivism is best understood by starting with its epistemological assump- tions. This is not a didactical decision; rather, it is because, for a positivist account of science, epistemology matters more than ontology. Scientific pri- ority is clearly given to epistemology. This is due to the privileged status of observation or, in other words, empirical experience. In positivism any statements about what exists depend on what we can know. What we can know in positivism is intimately linked to what we can observe/experience. As the latter question belongs to the domain of epistemology, the positivist account of science thus prioritizes epistemology over ontology. Epistemology is “philosophically prior” – it gives more importance to “what can be known by science” as compared to “what exists”. Empiricism The core epistemological position of positivism is empiricism. Empiricism in philosophy is a theory of knowledge (epistemology) which claims that there is (and must be) an empirical foundation for knowledge. Empirical experience is information perceived by the senses; knowledge ultimately results from sensual observation/experience. Hence, positivist science understands observation/ empirical experience to be a representation of reality, not reality itself – as we can only perceive “reality” through our senses. Consequently, only statements about phenomena that can be observed or that can be experienced count as knowledge. This means that only “observables” are the objects of scientific in- quiry in the positivist account of science and can be known by science. It thus follows that theories and hypotheses are only acceptable if they can be induc- tively proved, that is, proved through experience/observation. As an epistemological position, empiricism was largely developed through British Empiricism and is associated with the works of Francis Ba- con, Thomas Hobbes, John Locke, David Hume, and Adam Smith. In Unit 3, you will find core elements of their ideas of science in more detail. However, as will also be demonstrated in Unit 3, empiricism draws on a long historical tradition of philosophical thought that goes back to ancient Greece. The central features of empiricism become clearer when compared to the opposite position, called rationalism. Rationalism (from ratio, reason) is the epistemological assumption that knowledge mainly derives from human rea- son. It gives a privileged epistemological status to the human mind (and not to sensory, empirical experience). Rationalism as an epistemological position 45 also has a long tradition in European philosophy and is usually associated with the work of René Descartes, Baruch de Spinoza and Gottfried Wilhelm Leibniz. In fact, like empiricism, rationalism actually dates back to ancient Greece and the ideas of Aristotle and Plato. In short: in positivist science, knowledge derives from experience. Expe- rience is information received through the senses. Only statements about phenomena that can be directly experienced/observed can count as knowl- edge, whereas any statements that do not refer to the world of observable ob- jects cannot be granted the status of justified knowledge. Empiricism there- fore results in a scientific method which requires that all hypotheses and theo- ries must be tested against observations of the natural world. It is a belief that empirical validation or falsification is at the heart of real inquiry. Science is therefore considered to be methodologically empirical in nature. We will come back to the methodological aspects later in more detail. Materialism/physicalism/ontological naturalism The empiricist epistemological core position of positivism is easier to com- prehend when linked to the fundamental materialist ontology of positivism; this philosophical position is called materialism or often physicalism. Materi- alism/physicalism is the ontological assumption that reality ultimately con- sists of “matter”. According to this assumption, the world is a material world and “governed” by the laws of matter (nature). The position is sometimes al- so called ontological naturalism, in which everything is “nature” – with an understanding of “nature” as physical nature. Physical nature is material na- ture, hence the position’s interchangeable names of materialism, physicalism and ontological naturalism. A material/physical/natural world can be “observed” by the senses and thus be known, if not directly, then with the help of technological facilities such as microscopes, telescopes, laboratories, etc. The ontological position of materialism/physicalism/naturalism usually implies not only that the world is ultimately made of “matter”, but also that the human mind and consciousness belong to the material world as a result of their ultimately material/physical nature. This nature consists of nerve cells, neurons and the material structure of the brain, the activity of which can be observed for example in computer-assisted tomography. From a materialist ontological perspective, everything – including ideas and human thought – are ultimately attributed to matter. Here again the argument about ontological materialism/physiccalism/ naturalism should be exemplified by pointing to the opposite position, onto- logical idealism. From an idealist position, the world is ultimately made of 46 (immaterial) ideas, theories and mental constructs. The ontological idealist position goes back as far as Plato’s theory of forms (or theory of ideas), which states that reality consists of non-material, abstract forms or ideas and not the material world known to us through the senses. The forms or ideas are present “in” nature/matter (physis). These forms or ideas are understood to be distinct, singular extra-mental entities that are plurally represented “in” par- ticular material objects. Forms and ideas are the “essence” of material ob- jects: there is no being (ontology) of material objects without their intrinsic “idea” or form. For example, the idea or form of “circle” is represented by the many material things expressing the form of circles. The essence of all circles is the idea or form of “circle”. Forms and ideas are thus superordinate to matter. Ideas/forms are also transcendent to time and space; they are non- local and non-physical, even though they are real. The ideas and forms are often called the “universals” that are represented in the many particular things that we can see: the form/idea (universal) ”appears” to be material ob- jects (particulars). True knowledge is thus knowledge that the human mind gains about the world of ideas/forms. For Plato, evidence of the existence of abstract forms is by intuition. For example, a tool-maker’s blueprints provide evidence that forms/ideas are real and guide the practice of a manufacturer. Atomism/particularism/individualism The materialist ontology of positivism is an atomist one. Ontologically, atom- ism is the assumption that the (material) world is made up of the smallest in- divisible material particles or can ultimately be reduced to such elementary Download 0.79 Mb. Do'stlaringiz bilan baham: |
Ma'lumotlar bazasi mualliflik huquqi bilan himoyalangan ©fayllar.org 2024
ma'muriyatiga murojaat qiling
ma'muriyatiga murojaat qiling