Laclau and Mouffe: The Radical Democratic Imaginary
The hegemony debate: a defense of Stuart Hall
Download 0.72 Mb. Pdf ko'rish
|
The-Radical-Democratic-Imaginary-oleh-Laclau-and-Mouffe
The hegemony debate: a defense of Stuart Hall
The term, “hegemony,” is often read as a synonym for “domination.” Theorists working in the Gramscian tradition, however, take Gramsci’s “centaur” metaphor (1971:169–70) as their starting point. According to Gramsci, political authority in contemporary societies has two dimensions, force and the organization of consent. The organization of consent refers to the cultural dimension that is present in every political project, namely its promotion of popular identifications in terms of its corresponding imaginary. Again, Althusser holds that in a social formation that is structured by domination, a functional relationship will ultimately be established between the “repressive State apparatus” and the “Ideological State Apparatuses” (1971:150). Laclau and Mouffe would argue, by contrast, that social formations are never perfectly sutured together such that this sort of functional fit P OW E R A N D H E G E M O N Y 163 is obtained. 6 We will never find, for example, a perfect fit between governmental policies in the public education system and the goals of the global multi-media corporations. Private corporations can gain a marketing foothold in the classroom by sponsoring internet instruction. But, at the same time, students using the internet may get access to information about homosexuality, feminism, safer sex education and anti-corporate environmental activism that would have been otherwise difficult for them to obtain. Further, the disciplinary and cultural aspects of power are never neatly segregated in distinct institutions. There is, for example, a cultural moment in policing and a violent exclusionary moment in popular culture. While Foucault developed a highly sophisticated theory of disciplinary bio- power relations—which is in some ways remarkably similar to Gramsci’s conception of the organization of consent—he failed to give adequate attention to the presence of subtractive strategies within contemporary disciplinary regimes. Although Foucault asserts that bio-power fully displaced sovereign power during the early modern period, we are now witnessing the deployment of new forms of brutal subtractive power in key points within complex Western societies. When police and immigration officials brutally beat blacks, Latinos and Latinas only a few miles away from Los Angeles’ financial district, when it is revealed that that violence has become a systemic aspect of inner-city post-colonial policing, and when capitalist greed promises to produce increasingly large “surplus populations,” we can expect more and more complex articulations of brutal violence with disciplinary modes of social control. Instead of seeing power in terms of an either/or model— either brute subtractive domination or sophisticated productive bio-power normalization—we should think instead in terms of hybrid formations in which subtractive modes—domination, exclusion, genocide and so on—are combined with productive modes—the organization of consent. Hall’s interpretation of Thatcherism as a hegemonic formation (1988a) has been the subject of numerous debates. His critics claim that he portrayed Thatcherism as a dominant regime that had successfully incited the normalization and acceptance of its basic values (Jessop et al. 1988; Hirst 1989; Crewe 1988). However, when they point to opinion polls that apparently show that many of the people who voted for Thatcher actually disliked her policies, they miss the most innovative aspect of Hall’s argument. Hall did not actually claim that the Conservative Party had turned a majority of British voters into a camp of enthusiastic Thatcherites. He held that Thatcherism engaged in a hegemonic struggle in the following sense: it disorganized the prevailing political formation, namely the post-war bi-partisan consensus; it waged a cultural war to redefine key values in different spheres of the social: the economy, civil society, intellectual and moral life; it deployed a large and highly differentiated set of strategies; and it neutralized the opposition while creating a small group of fervent supporters who could synecdochically stand in for the whole electorate (1988a:7). It is of course true that the “pocket-book” strategy was one of the factors that contributed to Thatcher’s electoral success. Some key sectors of the voting population gained substantially from Thatcherite policies such as the deregulation P OW E R A N D H E G E M O N Y 164 of the private sector, tax-cutting schemes and the sale of council housing. But “pocket-book” politics cannot explain why the numbers of Thatcherite voters vastly exceeded the numbers of economic gainers, or why Thatcherism enjoyed substantial success in its bid to transform the entire political agenda and political culture. Hall usefully insists that “elections are not won or lost on so-called ‘real’ majorities, but on (equally real) ‘symbolic majorities’” (1988a:262). There is in fact substantial evidence that many voters supported Thatcher in spite of their dislike for her actual policies because she seemed to be a “strong leader,” and she made them feel “good to be British again.” Her success is also due in part to the fact that the Conservatives stigmatized the Labour Party by effectively associating it with unpopular groups such as militant trade unions, radical blacks and lesbians and gays (Smith 1994b:28–69). Only an analysis that combines the measurement of “pocket-book” politics with the study of political symbols and their material effects can adequately explain the paradoxical success of formations such as Thatcherism. Download 0.72 Mb. Do'stlaringiz bilan baham: |
Ma'lumotlar bazasi mualliflik huquqi bilan himoyalangan ©fayllar.org 2024
ma'muriyatiga murojaat qiling
ma'muriyatiga murojaat qiling