Laclau and Mouffe: The Radical Democratic Imaginary
“Methodology,” “family resemblances” and the study of
Download 0.72 Mb. Pdf ko'rish
|
The-Radical-Democratic-Imaginary-oleh-Laclau-and-Mouffe
“Methodology,” “family resemblances” and the study of
power Given the plurality of possible interpretations of gender, and the always shifting character of gender structures, theories that are based on the presumption of a natural unity among women, or a trans-historical and cross-cultural structure of women’s oppression, are problematic. However, this is not to say that we cannot conceptualize the continuities and linkages between different instances of women’s oppression. The challenge for feminist theory is to develop analyses of women’s oppression that capture institutionalized patterns of repetition without losing sight of contextually specific complexities. Following Laclau’s appropriation of Wittgenstein, we could say that social and political theory ought to trace patterns of repetition and institutionalization, but only in the form of non-essentialist “family resemblances” (Laclau 1990a:21–2, 29, 208–9, 214; Wittgenstein 1958: paras. 66, 69, 185–90; Staten 1984:13–14, 82). Here the limits of theory must be acknowledged. Strictly speaking, “methodology” is impossible, for the empirical and the transcendental always contaminate one another (Foucault 1970:318–22; Feyerabend 1993). At best, theory can make us more sensitive to the probability that hegemonic social forces will prevail to a greater or lesser degree in future P OW E R A N D H E G E M O N Y 160 contexts, but it can never fully predict those configurations. As we study different types of institutions and different discursive constructions of identities, we should expect to find a complicated network of similarities and differences between and among them. As we saw in Chapter 1, it is impossible to offer universal definitions of the relations between gender and the accumulation of surplus value, or between race and labor market segmentation. It is equally impossible to use a category such as gender to isolate a group of individuals and then offer universal statements about their condition without paying close attention to contextual specificity. The ways in which biological sex and gender structural positionings are overdetermined by other structures may mean that some women are positioned as oppressors and/or exploiters of other women (Alarcón 1990). We cannot, for example, construct a universal account that would explain the ways in which all women and girls are being affected by the globalization of industrial production. We could offer some generalizations, but we would also have to pay close attention to class, national, racial, ethnic, religious and other differences. We also have to anticipate the possibility that different women live their sex and gender structural positionings through antagonistic subject positions. Racially-constructed subject positions, for example, often give rise to intra-gender antagonisms. Where intra-gender antagonisms exist, feminist solidarity can only be constructed by working through these tensions; it cannot be assumed that such a solidarity is always already meaningful. Some features may be present across most of the sexist, racist, capitalist and homophobic structures that we study, but those features should not be treated as if they were essences. Other characteristics may emerge in only a few cases, but they should not be dismissed as irrelevant accidents or anomalies. We can trace the birth, extension and decline of specific apparatuses, but we will never find teleological and predictable patterns according to which history is supposed to unfold. From non-teleological, genealogical historical research (Foucault 1977) and “family resemblances” comparative research, we can suggest probable outcomes, but we cannot produce a perfectly accurate map of future social structures. As soon as we discover a “rule” that seems to govern the operation of a given institution in one context, we will find that that rule has to be more or less reformulated as we apply it to a different context. It is nevertheless crucially important that radical democratic theory traces systematic and yet incomplete patterns of repetitions, normalizations, and institutionalizations, for effective counter-hegemonic strategies must always take the prevailing configuration of power relations into account. It should also be recognized that Laclau adds a political supplement to Wittgenstein’s theory. Having displaced essence with “family resemblances,” Wittgenstein contends that the boundaries that shape meaning are built up over time as the members of the social group who share the language game in question engage in imperfectly repetitive usages. Laclau would add that the arbitrariness of the boundaries of meaning implies that the boundaries that do appear to operate as hard and fast rules—rules that seem to be absolutely necessary—only have that P OW E R A N D H E G E M O N Y 161 appearance thanks to the concealed effects of power relations. If it appears that only one form of “femininity,” “masculinity,” “marriage” or “the family” is “natural,” then what we are dealing with is concealed power. For this reason, apparently “neutral” terms can at times become the object of tremendous controversy. For example, conservatives from many countries criticized the United Nations’ documents relating to the 1995 International Conference On Women in Beijing because these texts used the term “gender” rather than “male” and “female.” It was alleged that “gender” signaled the promotion of homosexuality—since lesbianism, male homosexuality and transsexuality are understood by some conservatives as third, fourth and fifth genders—and the rejection of biologically- determined sex roles (Flanders 1997:7). Again, sexist, homophobic and other authoritarian forces are heavily invested in the maintenance of certain boundaries of meaning; they will always resist any analysis that challenges their attempts to govern the meaning of key terms. The very tools that we use to study power configurations may at times become the objects of political struggle. Critics of post-structuralist feminist theory have often argued that the claim that “woman” and “women” are nothing but strategic fictions ultimately undermines political solidarity. The response to such a charge is best stated in an almost self-contradictory manner. As Spivak argues, we inevitably speak in fictitious universalizing terms whenever we think strategically. The simple repudiation of all universalizing formulations in the name of theoretical correctness is not only a self-defeating gesture, but is often motivated by an unacknowledged claim to intellectual superiority. Spivak contends instead that we should engage in the impossible and yet tactically crucial attempt to master universalizing rhetoric where it may serve our purposes, and remain all the while vigilant about its totalizing effects. Universal claims, for all their fictitious character, can have tremendous pragmatic value as provisional starting points for activism; the task for radical democratic activists is to examine the ways in which they conceal antagonisms and foreclose alternative practices (1988a, 1988b; Spivak and Grosz 1990:11–12; Spivak et al 1990:117–18). Haraway points out that the female biological category is itself highly contested in scientific discourse, and that the mere fact that some persons share the common experience of being categorized as “female” does not automatically give rise to solidarity between them. Where some type of “gender consciousness” does become meaningful and effective, it does so in response to political contingencies. “Gender, race or class consciousness is an achievement forced on us by the terrible historical experience of the contradictory social realities of patriarchy, colonialism, and capitalism” (Haraway 1991:155). Although post-structuralist feminist theory shares many constructivist assumptions with Kuhn’s paradigm theory, it also suggests that there can only be a partial resolution to the process of discursive contestation in any given historical moment. Wherever sex and gender have become the sites of intense social contestation, many different gendering interpretative frameworks will compete with one another in their bid to hegemonize the social. Feminist interpretations P OW E R A N D H E G E M O N Y 162 of gender solidarity must struggle against the interest-driven “experts” who are deeply invested in the perpetuation of disciplinary constructions of the “woman” identity. Medical, psychoanalytic and aesthetic experts “do the work of limiting and regulating what it means to be a woman in line with the exigencies of their own discursive fields and legitimating truths” (Martin 1988:14). Regulatory discourses with tremendous authority are able not only to set the agenda on gender issues; they also establish the rules that shape the boundaries of acceptable discourse and set out in advance a table of the subjects who qualify for recognition as legitimate social agents. This is but one of the many double binds that feminism confronts: where feminists work to unify women, they must ensure that they are not doing so according to the terms established by the patriarchal “experts” and thereby unintentionally promoting reactionary gender frameworks and exclusions. Where the patriarchal “experts” build misogynist, racist and heterosexist elements into their apparently “natural” definition of “woman,” feminists must strive to ensure that their models of gender solidarity do not perpetuate these exclusions. The risk is that where the boundaries of the very categories that define the limits of feminist solidarity are rigidly determined in advance, some interests, issues and minority women subjects may be excluded. Butler contends that it is only a feminist movement that keeps the boundaries of feminist solidarity open to renegotiation that can avoid such exclusionary practices (Butler 1990a:15). Martin concludes that “the question for those of us engaged in the development of new forms of discourse is how to enter struggles over the meaning(s) of woman in ways that do not repress pluralities, without losing sight of the political necessity for fiction and unity” (Martin 1988:14). The fully constructivist conception of identity adopted by Butler and Laclau and Mouffe is therefore not incompatible with political strategizing. In some situations, their approach can be indispensable for theorizing radical democratic political practices. A rigorous application of constructivist theory would not contradict the discourses that call for feminist action against sexist forces; it would only contradict those arguments that take women’s unity as always already given. Download 0.72 Mb. Do'stlaringiz bilan baham: |
Ma'lumotlar bazasi mualliflik huquqi bilan himoyalangan ©fayllar.org 2024
ma'muriyatiga murojaat qiling
ma'muriyatiga murojaat qiling