Laclau and Mouffe: The Radical Democratic Imaginary
From organic crisis to the institutionalization of a new
Download 0.72 Mb. Pdf ko'rish
|
The-Radical-Democratic-Imaginary-oleh-Laclau-and-Mouffe
From organic crisis to the institutionalization of a new
imaginary Laclau and Mouffe’s theory of hegemony provides many valuable theoretical formulations that allow us to extend Butler’s and Hall’s analyses. Following Gramsci, Laclau insists in his early work that every analysis of a strategic discursive intervention must begin with historical contextualization. In what Gramsci calls an “organic crisis,” there is a dramatic collapse in popular identifications with institutionalized subject positions and political imaginaries. At this point, the prevailing discursive formations are peculiarly vulnerable to critique from any number of perspectives. The meaning of key signifiers, such as “democracy,” “freedom” and “equality,” are unusually available for multiple alternative articulations (Laclau 1977:103). Although identification with subject positions never fully meets the subject’s goal of making herself “at home” in her given structural positionings, she tends to experience the gap between the explanations provided by her subject positions and the material effects of her structural positionings in a particularly acute manner during an organic crisis. The 1960s in the United States is a case in point. Traditional patriotism failed to incite mass support for the Vietnam War, while traditional patriarchal, racial and political discourses were denounced as morally bankrupt by growing numbers of activists. In these and other similar conditions, we could say that more and more subjects become caught up in an “identity crisis”; their sense of alienation can become especially unbearable at this moment, such that their drive to seek out alternative explanatory frameworks is intensified. We should also note that in a fully-fledged breakdown of the social order, the experience of an identity crisis is shared not only by many of the disempowered but also by a significant proportion of the dominant groups as well. P OW E R A N D H E G E M O N Y 165 Hegemonic strategies are particularly effective during an organic crisis. More and more subjects become unusually open to innovative political discourses; they therefore begin to experience the network of social structures into which they have been thrown as antagonistically blocking them from becoming what they believe to be their true selves—a phantasmatic construction that is itself always shifting. As this experience of lack becomes more and more acute, competing political forces will attempt to “hegemonize” the social: they will attempt to offer their specific “systems of narration” as a compensatory framework, and they will represent that framework as the only one that can resolve the identity crisis (Laclau 1977:103; 1996h:44). The emerging hegemonic discourse works simultaneously to deepen the identity crisis by further undermining the crumbling traditional regime, to construct a new framework for identification, and to represent that framework as if it exhausted the terrain of legitimate discourse. Gramsci makes an important distinction between different strategic situations. In moments in which power is heavily concentrated in a singular state apparatus, as was the case in Tsarist Russia at the turn of the century, then resistance should be deployed according to a “war of maneuver” strategy: a single front that is mobilized directly against the single power center. In contemporary complex societies, however, we are rarely confronted with a situation in which power is heavily concentrated in a single center and wielded like a subtractive instrument according to a uniform logic. With Foucault, Gramsci contends that we are now generally confronted with situations in which power is concentrated in diverse institutional centers and deployed in complex and productive relations throughout the social according to multiple and hybrid logics. In these conditions, resistance should take the form of a “war of position”: a complex ensemble of struggles that take place at multiple strategic sites in state apparatuses, civil society and the family (Gramsci 1971:236–9). The multiple struggles that take place in a “war of position” deployment must be unified to gain maximum effectiveness, but in a site-specific manner such that their difference is not canceled out. In Gramsci’s terms, an increasingly sophisticated and strategically effective unifying strategy should move through three stages. In the first and crudest stage, a social movement is organized according to what Gramsci, invoking Hegel’s Philosophy of Right, calls its “economic- corporate” interests. At this stage, the social group’s solidarity is defined in the most particularistic terms. As the movement begins to act more and more as a hegemonic agent, redefining its demands in the light of other demands, and offering its discourse as a nodal point that symbolically sums up the interests of the other movements, it becomes first a “social class” and then a “party” (Gramsci 1971:181). The hegemonic discourse functions as the political “glue” that holds the historic bloc together as it stands in opposition against its enemy bloc. The process of this transition is enormously complicated, and involves complex reconstructions of identities and values. Further, each movement’s influence in these multilateral negotiations varies according to its institutionalized authority; I will return to this difficult problem in the Conclusion. P OW E R A N D H E G E M O N Y 166 Against Gramsci, Laclau and Mouffe argue that we cannot predict which movement will become the hegemonic agent, for this depends upon the specific conditions that obtain in a given historical formation. In his more recent work, Laclau also apparently differs with Gramsci in his emphasis on the formal character of hegemonic discourse. As we have seen, Laclau argues in these texts that the compelling aspect of a hegemonic discourse consists primarily in the orderly and coherent nature of its social imaginary, and not in its actual content. The difference between Laclau and Gramsci on this point is not as great as it may appear at first glance. Gramsci contends that although every party is in one sense “the expression of a social group,” a party can, in hegemonic conditions, “exercise a balancing and arbitrating function between the interests of their group and those of other groups, and succeed in securing the development of the group which they represent with the consent and assistance of the allied groups.” In an especially provocative phrase, he claims that the arbitration function of the party is analogous to that of the constitutional monarch who “reigns but does not govern,” and that the party must always strive “by various means to give the impression that it is working actively and effectively as an ‘impartial force’” (1971:148). In these passages, Gramsci refines his conception of hegemony: hegemony consists not merely in the unification of diverse social groups through articulation, but also in the construction of a political leadership that offers itself as an apparently “neutral space” for the inscription of a broad range of political demands—as nothing less than the horizon that makes all political discourse possible. This formal aspect of hegemonic discourse is also emphasized in Lefort’s analysis of what he calls the “invisible ideology” that prevails in contemporary Western societies. The discourse of consumption, for example, constructs an apparently closed universe in which multiple demands can be satisfied, but its framing function remains invisible insofar as totalization becomes latent. Following Baudrillard, Lefort suggests that our desire for a consumer product is not driven by any specific interest for that commodity in its particularity; on the contrary, we desire the Download 0.72 Mb. Do'stlaringiz bilan baham: |
Ma'lumotlar bazasi mualliflik huquqi bilan himoyalangan ©fayllar.org 2024
ma'muriyatiga murojaat qiling
ma'muriyatiga murojaat qiling