Laclau and Mouffe: The Radical Democratic Imaginary
Download 0.72 Mb. Pdf ko'rish
|
The-Radical-Democratic-Imaginary-oleh-Laclau-and-Mouffe
do with that tradition” (1996g:33).
In the cases in which racial minorities do embrace what Gilroy calls “ethnic absolutism” (1993), their projects can become antithetical to radical democratic pluralist values. Thomas notes, for example, that the apparently progressive conception of black “authenticity” is often used to disavow or to demonize lesbians and gays of color (1997). Attention should also be paid to the contexts in which “ethnic absolutism” thrives. It could be the case that such a phenomenon takes hold more effectively wherever the space for more democratic forms of expression are closed off by corporate, political and educational institutions. Norval suggests, for example, that dogmatic forms of resistance may become more compelling in conditions of severe economic deprivation and political, educational and cultural exclusions (1996:304). In an important intervention, Lubiano notes the parallels between the patriarchal and homophobic positions embraced by hegemonic factions within the black nationalist movement on the one hand and the moral authoritarianism of the prominent American new right/new racist/neo- conservative movements on the other. She contends that “even as [black nationalism] functions as resistance to the state…it reinscribes the state in particular M U LT I C U LT U R A L D I F F E R E N C E A N D T H E P O L I T I C A L 192 places within its own narratives of resistance. That reinscription most often occurs within black nationalist narratives of the black family” (Lubiano 1997:236). Laclau does not adequately acknowledge, however, the radical democratic pluralist potential that is expressed in the vast majority of anti-racist and radical multicultural struggles. These struggles affirm Baldwin’s principle: disempowered minorities ought to win recognition without being asked to pay the price of assimilation in return (Baldwin 1985:375). Far from isolating themselves from the dominant community, these struggles often attempt to subject dominant groups and hegemonic authoritarian values to the democratic critique that can be found in the discourses of the disempowered. Minority rights claims do sometimes take the form of a demand for separation, but they can also be phrased as radical communitarian demands for the authorization of an anti-racist, anti-sexist, anti- homophobic and anti-capitalist definition of “our common tradition” or “our shared values” (Williams 1995:82). Again, as Levine notes with respect to multicultural curricula, the aim is to value difference so that the operation of power— discrimination, exploitation and erasure—can be brought to light. A radical multiculturalism, for example, would not only celebrate democratic differences; it would also shed light on the power relations that structure cultural expression by studying, for example, trends in employment and the distribution of wealth, media ownership, affirmative action in universities, public arts grants and so on. Instead of thinking culture according to a simplistic pluralist logic, it would explore the complexities of transnational cultural appropriations, hybrid cultural articulations and intra-cultural antagonisms. 4 Against the weight of Laclau’s examples, I would argue that in contemporary American politics, the most dangerous forces of particularist politics actually favor dominant groups. The American wealthy are pursuing an increasingly segregationist agenda that is fundamentally eroding the concept of collective responsibility. Income taxes and capital gains taxes for the rich are cut, necessitating not only massive cuts in federal government programs, but also increases in the regional and local government taxes that are less fair for the lower-middle-class, workers and the poor. The geographical mobility of the poor is reduced through public transportation cuts while their already minuscule opportunity for socio-economic mobility is all but eliminated through education cuts. School zoning boundaries isolate the middle class from the rest of the population; school voucher programs and tax-free savings accounts transfer public funds from public school investment to subsidies for wealthy children’s private education; and local government tax schemes cut the wealthy suburban communities off from the inner city. Urban planning and policing techniques systematically protect the wealthy by cordoning off urban unrest and targeted forms of criminality (Davis 1991, 1992). Not-in- my-backyard-style lobbying by middle-class suburban communities has led to the concentration of environmental hazards in areas populated by the poor. The Republican Congress approved an experimental plan that sets up government subsidies for individuals who want to opt out of private group health insurance to obtain their own personal coverage. More and more corporations are eliminating M U LT I C U LT U R A L D I F F E R E N C E A N D T H E P O L I T I C A L 193 the pension plans that used to cover their entire work force and replacing them with generous tax-subsidized plans for the highest-paid managers. For the American wealthy, neo-conservative individualism and privatization are not enough; they are now demanding segregationist forms of individualism and privatization. Because race and class are so thoroughly intertwined in the United States (Takaki 1993; Omi and Winant 1994), much of these developments have an especially negative impact on the black and Latino communities, and on many Asian American communities as well. And yet, even as economic globalization and restructuration lock these peoples into perpetual poverty, and the backlashes against immigration, affirmative action, crime, teenage pregnancy, welfare, education spending and governmental excess are blatantly used to harness racist sentiment, dissimulation tactics are deployed such that the charge of racism becomes rebuttable. Bush puts Thomas on the Supreme Court, the media dwells on the O.J.Simpson case, the Republicans flirt with Colin Powell, Clinton launches a “national conversation” on race, and the Promise Keepers positions itself as a leader in the movement for multiracial harmony. 5 While Laclau’s critique of particularist politics is sound—and entirely compatible with Mouffe’s democratic theory—his emphasis on inappropriate strategic choices by ethnic and racial minorities is problematic. It is not clear, however, that Mouffe would agree with Laclau as he develops another aspect of his argument. I cannot assert a differential identity without distinguishing it from a context, and, in the process of making the distinction, 1 am asserting the context at the same time. And the opposite is true: I cannot destroy a context without destroying at the same time the identity of the particular subject who carries out the destruction. It is a very well known historical fact that an oppositionist force whose identity is constructed within a certain system of power is ambiguous vis-à-vis that system, because the latter is what prevents the constitution of the identity and it is, at the same time, its condition of existence. And any victory against the system also destabilizes the identity of the victorious force. (Laclau 1996g:27) It is once again rather difficult to assess this passage, for Laclau does not direct us towards the historical sources that he has in mind. In theoretical terms, Laclau— with reference once again to a hypothetical “ethnic minority”—argues that demands for “access to education, to employment, to consumer goods and so on…cannot be made in terms of difference, but [in terms] of some universal principles that the ethnic minority shares with the rest of the community” (1996g:28). From Laclau’s perspective, the danger is that progressive movements might stop short at aiming only to invert power relations, such that they neglect the importance of transforming the entire social structure. Assuming that a democratic M U LT I C U LT U R A L D I F F E R E N C E A N D T H E P O L I T I C A L 194 struggle’s opposition to a specific type of domination is integral to its identity, Laclau asserts that that struggle is always tempted to stop short at the mere inversion of the relation of domination, such that the logic of domination is largely preserved. If the oppressed is defined by its difference from the oppressor, such a difference is an essential component of the identity of the oppressed. But in that case, the latter cannot assert its identity without asserting that of the oppressor as well. (Laclau 1996g:29) We could note, in passing, that Žižek similarly contends that “each position is only its negative relation to the other” and that “man is a reflexive determination of woman’s impossibility of achieving an identity with herself (which is why woman is a symptom of man)” (Žižek 1990:253). 6 Referring to Norval’s research on apartheid and to the dimensions of South Africa’s post-apartheid society, Laclau comments, If we simply invert the relation of oppression, the other (the former oppressor) is maintained as what is now oppressed and repressed, but this inversion of the contents leaves the form of oppression unchanged. (1996g:31) Although Laclau originally wrote these passages in 1991, and published them in 1995 and 1996, he does not actually examine South Africa’s contemporary history to investigate whether or not this simple inversion took place. Based on the information that we have available about the transition process, the new South African Constitution, the policies of the African National Congress (ANC), and the bi-partisan pattern of cooperation with Bishop Tutu’s Truth and Reconciliation Commission, we would estimate that the ANC itself never really needed Laclau’s warning. Ash comments, Of course, history knows many examples of people who fought heroically against one dictatorship, only themselves to erect another one. But the fight against apartheid inside South Africa also nourished a feisty attachment to democracy, and the ANC movement is itself a rainbow coalition. (1997:10–11) Norval estimates that the ANC government has been particularly impressive in its deployment of affirmative action and equal opportunity programs, and in its interpretation of non-racist discourse such that the latter has become consistent with these programs. She notes, however, that the ANC’s record with respect to the colored population and the labor movement is less than perfect (1996:294– 6). There are social agents in South Africa who actually do continue to threaten M U LT I C U LT U R A L D I F F E R E N C E A N D T H E P O L I T I C A L 195 to perpetuate the “closed, organic identities” that were central to apartheid discourse, namely the far right, the new National Party and Buthelezi’s Inkatha (1996:302). This complex map of social agents does not, however, correspond to Laclau’s model of a formerly oppressed agent who merely inverts the prevailing power relations. Even the racist Inkatha cannot be held up as an example in this regard, for with its historical record of cooperation with the apartheid regime and its embrace of free market principles, its positions within the prevailing configurations of power relations are multiple and complex in nature. Laclau’s emphasis on the danger of an oppressed group embracing a strategy of simple inversion also seems to be at odds with Mouffe’s approach, for Mouffe consistently affirms the complex character of the social, and the plural, overlapping and even contradictory character of the social spheres and institutions in which antagonisms develop. Even in those conditions in which two chains of equivalence (racist/anti-racist; capitalist/anti-capitalist; etc.) stand antagonistically opposed to one another in what appears to be a total struggle at one site in the social, the ethical “universe” in which each element in those chains orients itself will always extend beyond the site of the antagonism. A student group, for example, might throw itself into a bitter struggle against a university administration, but, even in the most antagonistic circumstances, its discourse will be influenced by sources outside that site, such as the students’ links with other struggles and their previous residential communities. Even in a total war situation, such as the anti-apartheid struggle in South Africa, the terms of the struggle always go far beyond the oppressor/oppressed dyad. Anti-apartheid organizations, for example, drew extensively upon traditions of anti-imperialist struggles throughout Africa and the developing world, the democratic struggles of racial minorities in Europe and the United States, and the socialist tradition. It is precisely this richness of overdetermination that infinitely postpones the moment in which an oppositional struggle would inhabit such an impoverished ethical universe that it would aim simply to “invert” the prevailing power relations without altering their content. Norval contends that the non-racist aspect of the discourse that was embraced by the majority of anti-apartheid activists was in fact strengthened by its opposition to the apartheid regime, for the régime placed before their eyes the utterly brutal consequences of an identitary political logic (1996:304). Laclau’s overall emphasis remains firmly centered on a critique of Western Eurocentrism and on an investigation of the conditions necessary for opening communitarian universalistic principles to democratic contestation (1996g:34– 5). He recognizes that the “struggles of new social actors show that the concrete practices of our society restrict the universalism of our political ideals to limited sectors of the population” (1996g:34). It could be argued, however, that his assessment of the political context of these struggles is insufficient. Again, the weight of his examples tend to suggest that the dangers of particularistic discourse reside, for the most part, among racial and ethnic minorities. I have argued, by contrast, that in contemporary American politics, it is mainly the wealthy—an M U LT I C U LT U R A L D I F F E R E N C E A N D T H E P O L I T I C A L 196 overwhelmingly white Anglo population—that is embracing the new segregationism. Further, Laclau comments that “the decline of the integrationist abilities of the Western states makes political conformism a rather unlikely outcome” (1996g:34). While it is certainly true that we are currently witnessing a dramatic shrinkage in the welfare state and massive cuts in public programs, the situation with respect to political conformism may be much more complicated than Laclau’s diagnosis would suggest. First, we should note that the current transformations in the state structures are uneven in nature. As Fraser, citing Skocpol, notes, the state is not a singular entity; it is instead a “complex and polyvalent nexus of compromise formations in which are sedimented the outcomes of past struggles as well as the conditions for present and future ones” (1989:157). In the United States, huge cuts are being made in education, welfare and health programs, but massive expansions in policing, high technology domestic surveillance, border patrols, immigration monitoring, penitentiary systems, and the tracking of welfare recipients are taking place. We are witnessing an acceleration in the differentiation of social control technologies as bio-power strategies are deployed with more and more productive finesse in the disciplining of the middle-class and professional strata, while the brute tactics of banishment and capital punishment—tactics that Foucault believed had been more or less replaced in the early modern era (Foucault 1979)—are routinely used against the dangerously unassimilable elements of the “underclass.” Norval argues that the apartheid regime was supported by a dual strategy: the organization of consent among the “insiders” and the deployment of brute force against the “outsiders” (1996:4). It is perhaps the case that this aspect of apartheid logic, namely its “combined and uneven development”—its articulation of multiple modes of power relations in complex overdetermined formations—is exemplary with respect to the emerging structure of American society rather than exceptional. The political center and the right have virtually declared a war on what they call the “underclass,” the disproportionately non- white impoverished peoples of the inner cities. (We could note here that poor of the rural areas and indigenous peoples on remote reservations have all but disappeared from public discourse altogether.) These peoples are not only blamed for their own impoverishment; they are increasingly constructed as sub-humans who, because of their anti-social cultural traditions and biological tendencies towards addiction, excessive sexuality, criminality and inferior intelligence, simply cannot be helped through education and skill training. Popular texts such as The Download 0.72 Mb. Do'stlaringiz bilan baham: |
Ma'lumotlar bazasi mualliflik huquqi bilan himoyalangan ©fayllar.org 2024
ma'muriyatiga murojaat qiling
ma'muriyatiga murojaat qiling