Leonid Zhmud The Origin of the History of Science in Classical Antiquity
Download 1.41 Mb. Pdf ko'rish
|
The Origin of the History of Science in
Fragmente der griechischen Historiker, if “the modern notions of an objective
historical research” are applied? From the viewpoint of the present-day criteria, Eudemus’ works belong to the history of science only with some reservation. Even more reservations can be held concerning Theophrastus’ doxography, es- pecially concerning Meno’s doxography. In applying rigid criteria to the first specimen of newly-born genres, however, we should be aware of the limitation of this procedure, which, though quite legitimate, is hardly the only correct one. On the contrary, the historical approach to the project of the Lyceum shows that, in spite of all the differences between the Peripatetic historiography of science and philosophy and its contemporary counterpart, the latter is deeply rooted in the ancient tradition, which in turn begins with Aristotle and his all these other fields of civilization.” (Jaeger, W. Rec.: Cherniss, H. Aristotle’s Criti- cism of Presocratic Philosophy, AJP 58 [1937] 354). 75 See above, 111 f. Hussey, E. Aristotle and mathematics, Science and mathematics in ancient Greek culture, ed. by C. J. Tuplin, T. E. Rihll, Oxford 2002, 217–229. 76 On Aristotle’s contribution to the development of historical research, see von Fritz. Die Bedeutung des Aristoteles für die Geschichtsschreibung, 91ff.; Weil, R. Aristote et l’histoire, Paris 1960; idem. Aristotle’s view of history, Articles on Aristotle 2. Ethics and politics, ed. by J. Barnes et al., London 1977, 202–217; Huxley, G. On Aristotle’s historical methods, GRBS 13 (1972) 157–169; De Ste. Croix, op. cit.; Blum, op. cit., 20ff. 77 Baltussen, H. A ‘dialectical’ argument in De anima A 2–4, Polyhistor. Studies in the history and historiography of ancient philosophy presented to J. Mansfeld, ed. by K. Algra et al., Leiden 1996, 335f. Chapter 4: The historiographical project of the Lyceum 136 school. Thus, without identifying Peripatetic historiography with modern his- toriography, we have every reason to compare them, particularly since we are dealing with the development of one and the same phenomenon. To realize better the importance that the Peripatetics attached to îstoría, we should bear in mind the following. First, the Aristotelian theory of science stresses the empirical origin of any knowledge. The question Ôti, ‘that (some- thing is the case)’, i.e., the collection and description of facts, not only precedes the question dióti, ‘why (something is the case)’, i.e., the explanation of gen- eral or particular causes, but actually makes it possible in the first place. 78 Thus, any scientific explanation is based on the facts established by observation (fai- nómena) and correspondingly arranged beforehand. 79 In this sense, even a purely descriptive work is a necessary part of scientific procedure inasmuch as it is the prerequisite for subsequent theoretical analysis; and the Peripatetics, as we know, wrote hundreds of such works. In natural sciences, the questions about facts and about their causes can be asked within the framework of two different types of research, empirical and theoretical, which nevertheless be- long to the same science, e.g. zoology (physics). 80 What the Peripatetics related to the field of natural history (fusik3 îstoría), 81 however, was not just a loosely arranged collection of facts lacking any analysis. For example, two of Theophrastus’ works, Historia plantarum and De causis plantarum, are de- voted to research on Ôti and on dióti respectively. In Historia plantarum, how- ever, we find not merely assembled data but botanical classification, morphol- ogy, and taxonomy. Second, for Aristotle and the Lyceum as a whole, natural history was not yet rigidly separated from the history of human deeds and events, îstoríai perì tõn práxewn. 82 Comparing the contents of Theophrastus’ (fr. 196a FHSG), Aristoxenus’ (fr. 131), and Hieronymus of Rhodes’ (fr. 35–36) identically en- 78 Ôti mèn gàr oÛtw tañta sumbaínei, d4lon ëk t4~ îstoría~ t4~ fusik4~, dióti dé, nñn skeptéon (De inc. an. 704b 9). See also HA 491a 7–14, PA 646a 8–12. 79 E.g. Download 1.41 Mb. Do'stlaringiz bilan baham: |
Ma'lumotlar bazasi mualliflik huquqi bilan himoyalangan ©fayllar.org 2024
ma'muriyatiga murojaat qiling
ma'muriyatiga murojaat qiling