Leonid Zhmud The Origin of the History of Science in Classical Antiquity
Download 1.41 Mb. Pdf ko'rish
|
The Origin of the History of Science in
op. cit., 129.
118 For parallels between Aristotle’s mathematical passages and Eudemus’ History of Geometry, see below, 197 f., 202f. The material of the History of Theology overlaps that of the Metaphysics and On Philosophy (see above, 131 n. 53). On Theophrastus’ dependence on Aristotle, see McDiarmid, J. B. Theophrastus on Presocratic causes, HSCPh 61 (1953) 85–156; Mansfeld. Aristotle. 119 He wrote about Anaximander, Anaximenes, Anaxagoras, Empedocles, Archelaus, Democritus, Diogenes, and Metrodorus (D.L. V, 42–44, 49). Besides, he could have used the material of Aristotle’s monographs on Xenophanes, Alcmaeon, and Melis- sus (D. L. V, 25). 120 Interestingly, Theophrastus wrote a special work on Hippocrates of Chios’ student Aeschylus (D. L. V, 50 = 137 No. 42 FHSG) but seemed not to mention him in the Physiko¯n doxai (cf. above, 132 n. 63); on Menestor, see below, 158 n. 166. 121 Casadio, G. Eudemo di Rodi: Un pioniere della storia delle religioni tra Oriente e Occidente, WS 112 (1999) 39–54. 122 On Hippon, cf. 38 A 6 (= Arist. Met. 984a 3) and A 3–4, 10, 13–14, etc. (from Theophrastus), A 11 (from Meno). Aristotle only once refers to Philolaus’ oral dic- tum ( EE 1225a 30) and ascribes his astronomical system to anonymous ‘Pythago- reans’. Theophrastus and Meno attribute specific theories to Philolaus (44 A 16–23, 27). Chapter 4: The historiographical project of the Lyceum 146 the question of the nature of the sun (II, 20); 123 none of them concurs with the solution offered by Aristotle and Theophrastus (the sun consists, like the other celestial bodies, of the fifth element, ether). 124 What was the purpose of collect- ing them? It is very unlikely that they intended to turn to this problem again after enriching themselves with new – or rather with old – knowledge. This col- lection was mainly of historical interest, showing the difficult path to the truth that was finally revealed in Aristotle’s and Theophrastus’ physical teaching, i.e., outside of the Physiko¯n doxai. 125 Aristotle attributed to facts an independent value. These acquire even great- er significance when, properly selected and arranged, they help in the search for the ‘causes’ (dióti). Although explaining the ‘causes’ was not among the im- mediate tasks of the historiographical project, this does not mean that the Peri- patetics limited their studies to particular facts. The discoveries of the scientists and the opinions of the philosophers, doctors, and theologians not only paved the way for conclusions of a general character, they themselves had already been selected and arranged in accordance with Aristotle’s theoretical views on science and its development. This means that the conclusions, as so often, were known in advance. Thus, e.g., at the beginning of his History of Geometry, Eudemus states a general rule of cognitive evolution from aÍsqhsi~ to logis- mó~ and further to noñ~ (fr. 133), and this is not the only case in which philo- sophical ideas were applied to historical material (5.4). Speaking of the original objectives of the Peripatetic project, one has to bear in mind one important circumstance. In terms of their literary form, neither Eudemus’ histories, nor Theophrastus’ doxography can be regarded as ‘eso- teric’ writings, pragmateiai, intended only for use in the Lyceum. In spite of the certainly not easily digestible subject matter of these works, both their form and their subsequent fate strongly imply that, just like the Download 1.41 Mb. Do'stlaringiz bilan baham: |
Ma'lumotlar bazasi mualliflik huquqi bilan himoyalangan ©fayllar.org 2024
ma'muriyatiga murojaat qiling
ma'muriyatiga murojaat qiling