Leonid Zhmud The Origin of the History of Science in Classical Antiquity
Download 1.41 Mb. Pdf ko'rish
|
The Origin of the History of Science in
op. cit., 100), which re-
ferred to doxography, rather than to the history of science. 5. Eudemus’ history of science 149 renowned as a geometer; it is only in a historical context that such a figure could have been mentioned. It would not be surprising if one and the same mathematician, e.g. Hippo- crates, appeared to be mentioned by Eudemus in connection with the problem of doubling the cube along with Archytas and Eudoxus, while figuring at the same time along with Antiphon in connection with squaring the circle. Such re- peated references are typical for any history of science. Apart from that, Eude- mus could well have deviated from the chronological principle of organizing the material while discussing problems that had preoccupied several gener- ations of geometers. On the whole, however, as we see from the Catalogue, he proceeded from generation to generation, from teachers to their disciples, rather than from one problem to another. 131 It is difficult, e.g., to suppose that Eudemus should have considered together the three authors of Elements he mentions, rather than in chronological order. In exactly the same way, the His- tory of Astronomy was not organized in accordance with the problems (the moon’s eclipses, the order of the planets, the position of the earth, and so on), but in accordance with the pro¯tos heurete¯s principle. Eudemus preferred the chronological arrangement even in the History of Theology, where much more limited material referred to the history of one single problem, the principles of the theologians, and easily allowed systematization by their number or type. Since the formula prõto~ eûret2~ is found, full or abridged, in practically every fragment of Eudemus’ works on the history of science, they can be re- garded, in their entirety, as a detailed answer to the question: ‘who discovered what?’. In seven of the nine fragments of the History of Geometry that reached us under the name of Eudemus, we find either prõto~, or eÛrhma (eÛresi~, eûrískw ) or both of them in combination. 132 Clear traces of this terminology have survived in the Catalogue as well: prõton eûr2sqai in connection with the invention of geometry in Egypt ( In Eucl., 64.18), prõto~ and e0ren on Thales (65.7f.), @neñre on Pythagoras (65.21), eûrøn and prõto~ on Hippo- crates (66.4f.), eûre$n on Leon (66.22), prõto~ on Eudoxus (67.2f.), and @neñre on Hermotimus (67. 20f.). No less revealing are those testimonies on geometers that can be safely related to the History of Geometry. 133 Further, 131 Heath. Elements I, 38; Edelstein, op. cit., 95. Pappus (Coll. IV, 272.15f.) and Euto- cius ( In Archim. De sphaer., 57.13f.), on the contrary, could consider different so- lutions of the same problem without regard to their authors’ chronology or even their names. See Knorr. TS, 77ff., 213ff. 132 toñto tò qeørhma eûrhménon ûpò Qaloñ prøtou (fr. 135), eÛresi~ (fr. 136), eûr2mata tõn Puqagoreíwn (fr. 137), Oınopídou eÛrhma (fr. 138), ˆIppo- kráth~ kaì ^Antifõn zht2sante~ … eûr2kasin (fr. 139), ûf’ ˆIppokrátou~ ëgráfhsan prøtou (fr. 140), ^Arcútou eÛrhsi~ (fr. 141). 133 See below, 170ff. In the material on Thales, prõto~ and eÛresi~ are mentioned (In Eucl., 250.20f.); in that on the Pythagoreans, eÛrhma (Schol. in Eucl., 273.3–13, twice); on Oenopides, prõto~ (In Eucl., 283.7f.); on Hippocrates, prõto~ and e0ren in Proclus (213.7f.) and prõto~ in Eratosthenes (Eutoc. In Archim. De Chapter 4: The historiographical project of the Lyceum 150 prõto~ eûret2~ is mentioned in five of the seven fragments of the History of Download 1.41 Mb. Do'stlaringiz bilan baham: |
Ma'lumotlar bazasi mualliflik huquqi bilan himoyalangan ©fayllar.org 2024
ma'muriyatiga murojaat qiling
ma'muriyatiga murojaat qiling