Leonid Zhmud The Origin of the History of Science in Classical Antiquity
Download 1.41 Mb. Pdf ko'rish
|
The Origin of the History of Science in
Astronomy, whereas an excerpt of this work, analogous to but much shorter
than the Catalogue, is entitled: tí~ tí e0ren ën maqhmatiko$~ ; 134 We have noted already that the search for discoverers, which had mightily stimulated the formation of the history of culture, remained topical in the Ly- ceum as well. Some of the Peripatetics paid a direct tribute to the genre of heurematography in works bearing the standard title of On Discoveries. 135 Nor did Aristotle ignore this subject matter himself. 136 Considering that in philo- sophical biography discoveries are a recurrent topic, it could well go back to Aristoxenus, the founder of the genre. 137 His biography of Pythagoras ascribes to the philosopher the introduction in Greece of measures and weights and the identification of the Evening and the Morning Stars with Venus (fr. 24). A frag- ment of his work On Arithmetic says that Pythagoras advanced the science of numbers discovered by the Egyptian god Thoth (fr. 23). Extracts from other bi- ographies by Aristoxenus (who wrote on Socrates, Plato, and Archytas) unfor- tunately do not contain any similar information, but his work On Music is brim- ming with references to various discoveries (fr. 78–81, 83), as is the history of music by Heraclides of Pontus (fr. 157–159, 163). Dicaearchus developed this subject in his works on musical agones (fr. 75–76, 85), and in his Life of Hellas did not fail to mention the discovery of horse-breeding by the Egyptian king Se- sostris (fr. 57). Still more important is the subject of the first discoverers in the histories of various técnai written by Aristotle; it is presented in doxography as well. 138 Persistent interest in cultural novelties and their authors is thus typical of the majority of the historically oriented genres practiced in the Lyceum. The influence the early heurematographic tradition exercised on these genres had various forms and gradations. While Peripatetic heurematography provides an example of the direct continuity of genre, individual references to discoveries in the context of a biography or a systematic treatise testify rather to the thematic continuity. The most interesting case seems to be where the prin- sphaer., 88.18–23); on Democritus, prõto~ (Archim. II, 430.5f.); on Archytas, prõto~ (D. L. VIII, 83); and on Eudoxus, ëxhúrhken prõto~ (Archim. II, 430.1f.). 134 Fr. 144, 145, 146, 147, 148; Ps.-Heron. Def., 166.23–168.12. = Eud. fr. 145. 135 Heraclides Ponticus (fr. 152), Theophrastus (fr. 728–734 FHSG), Strato (fr. 144– 147). 136 Fr. 382, 479, 501, 600, 602 Rose = fr. 924 Gigon; see Eichholtz, op. cit., 24f.; Wend- ling, op. cit. 137 Leo, op. cit., 46f., 99f.; see above, 35 n. 60. 138 See above, 137f. Aristotle regarded Thales as the founder of physics ( Met. 983b 20), Empedocles of rhetoric, Zeno of dialectic (fr. 65 Rose), and Socrates of ethics ( Met. 1078b 17). Particularly numerous are the mentions of prõto~ in the historical over- view of the @rcaí in Metaphysics A: Hesiod or Parmenides (984b 23, 31), Empe- docles (985a 8, 29), Pythagoreans (985b 23), and Xenophanes (986b 21). Theo- phrastus follows and develops these ideas (fr. 225, 226a, 227d–e, 228a FHSG). 5. Eudemus’ history of science 151 ciple of pro¯tos heurete¯s becomes the constitutive feature of a historical treatise, for example in Aristotle’s Tecnõn sunagwg2 (and, earlier, in Glaucus of Rhe- gium) or, after him, in Eudemus’ history of science. 139 It is important to point out, though, that this principle as such is by no means identical to the historical approach. No wonder then that the Peripatetic heurematography features tradi- tional discoverers, rather than real innovators of the historical epoch, let alone scientists. 140 The attention is invariably focused on cultural innovations as such, constituting a list that is not ordered systematically or chronologically. Unlike heurematography, the history of various arts and sciences (rhetoric, poetry, or mathematics) attempts to show the dynamic of their development and does not base the account on the list of discoveries, but on the chronology of their au- thors, thus giving it a historical perspective. In the history of science, Eudemus could employ a chronological approach much more consistently than his colleagues, owing mostly to the character of his material. In fact, in this period, the cumulative development of the exact sciences was much more obvious than that of physics or medicine. The dis- coveries of mathematicians necessarily depended on what had been achieved before them: Hippocrates and Theaetetus relied on Pythagorean mathematics, Archytas and Eudoxus developed the theories of Hippocrates, etc. A mathema- tician could base his research on a solid foundation created by his predecessors and move further in his quest for the truth faster than the others. To be sure, Eudemus records in details some unsuccessful attempts to solve mathematical problems, e.g. Antiphon’s squaring of the circle (fr. 139–140). It is, however, in the nature of mathematics that its history includes many more victories than failures, especially in comparison with other sciences. No wonder that, in the history of early Greek geometry, Eudemus encountered fewer cases in which many scientists failed to solve one and the same problem than in the history of physics. Each of the geometers mentioned by Eudemus could claim credit for real discoveries that allowed them to be listed among the Download 1.41 Mb. Do'stlaringiz bilan baham: |
Ma'lumotlar bazasi mualliflik huquqi bilan himoyalangan ©fayllar.org 2024
ma'muriyatiga murojaat qiling
ma'muriyatiga murojaat qiling