Leonid Zhmud The Origin of the History of Science in Classical Antiquity
Download 1.41 Mb. Pdf ko'rish
|
The Origin of the History of Science in
Eudemus of Rhodes, 25ff.
142 See below, 232 n. 18. 143 The Magi and Egyptians (fr. 6 Rose = fr. 23 Gigon, with a parallel reference to Eude- mus), Orpheus (fr.7a Rose = fr.26 Gigon), the Seven Sages (fr.3a–b Rose = fr.28–29 Gigon). Cf. above, 113 n. 154. 6. Doxography: between systematics and history 153 6. Doxography: between systematics and history A different lot fell to the principle of pro¯tos heurete¯s in doxography. It was predetermined, in many respects, by the purposes of Theophrastus’ work and the character of his material. Doxography aimed to describe all the (relevant) doxai, and not only the true ones. In a word, its subject was the historically re- corded opinions of physicists. This task dictated another method of arranging the material, differing from that employed in the history of science. Apart from the opinions true from the viewpoint of Peripatetic physics, which could be qualified as discoveries and presented in chronological order, Theophrastus had to register a great deal of wrong opinions. In physics, as in medicine, studied by Meno, firm proofs were often lacking and it was difficult to distinguish true opinions from false ones. The ideas of an earlier thinker could seem sounder than those suggested later, so that a ‘progressive’ scheme of things did not al- ways work. Furthermore, Theophrastus had to deal with many identical opinions on the same problem, e.g. whether the cosmos is eternal or not. 144 In the history of geometry, such a situation was hardly possible: after a theorem has been proven, one can try for a more elegant or simpler proof, but no one would simply state the same as it regularly happened in physics. Thus, Eude- mus gives several successive solutions of the problem of doubling the cube, which from the mathematical point of view are really different. In the history of astronomy, for any important discovery (e.g. that the moon reflects the sun’s light or that the angle of the obliquity of ecliptic is equal to 24°), Eudemus ap- parently registered its immediate author alone, without mentioning all those who shared this view. Finally, Peripatetic physics covered a much wider range of problems than any mathematical science: it included matters that concern physics, astronomy, and meteorology, as well as psychology, physiology, em- bryology, and even geography (on the Nile’s floods, Aët. IV, 1) As a result, the number of various doxai – opposite, similar, or identical – that were included in the doxography, as well as the number of their authors, greatly exceeded the relatively limited material that Eudemus had worked on. Together with the distinctive features of the physical opinions that had to be fitted to the Procrustean bed of the Peripatetic categories, this factor largely predetermined the complicated structure of the Physiko¯n doxai, which com- bined several principles of arranging material. Some of them were used in the earliest doxographical accounts, others were developed by Aristotle. Herodo- tus, as far as we can judge, used the chronological principle, 145 Hippias ar- 144 Aët. II, 4 (eı Áfqarto~ ô kósmo~): Anaximander, Anaximenes, Anaxagoras, Archelaus, Diogenes, Leucippus: the cosmos is perishable; Xenophanes, Parme- nides, Melissus: the cosmos is eternal. 145 His doxographical overview of the theories explaining the causes of the Nile’s floods (II, 20–23) contains the opinions (without mentioning any names) of Thales, Euthy- menes of Massalia (rendered by Hecataeus), and Anaxagoras. Cf. FGrHist 1 F 302; 647 F 1, 5 and 2, 1–3 (= Aët. IV,1.1–3); Jacoby, F. Euthymenes von Massalia, RE 6 Chapter 4: The historiographical project of the Lyceum 154 ranged the ideas in accordance with their supposed relationship and similarity, while Gorgias and Isocrates classified the material by the character and/or the number of the principles admitted by the given philosopher. 146 In Physics I, 2 Aristotle characterized the Presocratics’ principles according to the scheme that goes back to Plato’s method of division (diaíresi~): there must be either one principle or many; if one, it must be either motionless or in motion; if many, then either limited (two, three, four, etc.) or unlimited plurality; if unlimited, then either one in kind or different in kind. Since Aristotle cites but a few names here (Parmenides, Melissus, Democritus), it is obvious that the systematic as- pect of the doctrine of principles was more interesting to him than the historical one. In the doxographical section of Download 1.41 Mb. Do'stlaringiz bilan baham: |
Ma'lumotlar bazasi mualliflik huquqi bilan himoyalangan ©fayllar.org 2024
ma'muriyatiga murojaat qiling
ma'muriyatiga murojaat qiling