Leonid Zhmud The Origin of the History of Science in Classical Antiquity
Download 1.41 Mb. Pdf ko'rish
|
The Origin of the History of Science in
forthcoming).
104 Cf. Runia. What is doxography?, 51. 105 Hdt. II, 20–23 presents one of the earliest doxographical overviews on the Nile’s floods. Chapter 4: The historiographical project of the Lyceum 142 ing to this procedure any independent value that might be described in terms of historical interest. The doxographical overview at the beginning of the Meta- physics undoubtedly reveals such an interest. 106 Certainly, the material of Aris- totle’s doxographical overviews, the opinions of physicists, was directly related to his scientific and philosophical views, so that it is quite natural to expect here much aberration and subjectivism. But even these features reflect, to a large ex- tent, his historical views, rather than prove that ideas of his precursors were im- portant to him only insofar as they could provide material for the construction of his theories. 107 As W. Jaeger acutely observed, Aristotle “was the first thinker to set up … a conception of his own position in history”; he invented “the notion of intellectual development in time and regards even his own achievements as the result of an evolution dependent solely on its own laws.” 108 From this per- spective, the opinions of the Presocratics were, naturally, regarded as a prelimi- nary stage for Aristotle’s own theories. No wonder Theophrastus interpreted them in Peripatetic terms, quite often making the earlier thinkers answer ques- tions that they had never formulated themselves. This prompts us to treat Theophrastus’ interpretations with much caution, but hardly casts doubt on the historical orientation of his Physiko¯n doxai. Theophrastus’ Physiko¯n doxai and especially Eudemus’ history of the the- oretical sciences were much less related to the problems of their own theoreti- cal works than Aristotle’s doxographical overviews. Eudemus was neither a mathematician, nor an astronomer, nor a theologian, and could not regard the heroes of his histories as his predecessors. Theophrastus was a fusikó~, but his own Physics, if we judge from the preserved fragments, followed Aris- totle’s Physics, i.e., developed contemporary fusik3 ëpist2mh, leaving aside the fusikõn dóxai that he had collected. 109 It is revealing that Democritus is nearly the only Presocratic mentioned in the fragments of Theophrastus’ Physics (fr. 238 FHSG), except for the controversial reference to Xeno- phanes. 110 Therefore, the thesis that Theophrastus systematized the opinions of 106 See below, 154f. 107 As H. Cherniss thought ( Aristotle’s criticism of Presocratic philosophy, Baltimore 1935, 347ff.). 108 Jaeger. Aristotle, 3. 109 Though it is possible that Theophrastus’ Physics was written before Physiko¯n doxai, doxographical passages in his systematic works are generally very rare: Gottschalk, H. Rec., Gnomon 39 (1967) 20. Cf. below, 144 n. 115, 158 n. 166. Eudemus’ Physics, although it contains many such passages (see below, 152 n. 141), followed Aristotle’s Physics even more closely than Theophrastus’, sometimes nearly para- phrasing it. It is unlikely that Eudemus’ used Theophrastus’ doxography. 110 Qeófrasto~ ën to$~ Fusiko$~ gégrafen (fr. 232 FHSG). This reference can be either from Theophrastus’ Physics or from his Physiko¯n doxai. See Steinmetz, P. Die Physik des Theophrastos von Eresos, Bad Homburg 1964, 334ff.; Sharples, R.W. Theophrastus on the heavens, Download 1.41 Mb. Do'stlaringiz bilan baham: |
Ma'lumotlar bazasi mualliflik huquqi bilan himoyalangan ©fayllar.org 2024
ma'muriyatiga murojaat qiling
ma'muriyatiga murojaat qiling