Leonid Zhmud The Origin of the History of Science in Classical Antiquity
Download 1.41 Mb. Pdf ko'rish
|
The Origin of the History of Science in
RhM 42 (1887) 7.
163 Diels believed that Simplicius borrowed these fragments from Alexander ( Dox., 108f.; McDiarmid, op. cit., 90f.), but see Reinhardt, K. Parmenides und die Ge- schichte der griechischen Philosophie, Bonn 1916, 92 n. 1; Regenbogen. Theo- phrast, 1536; von Kienle, op. cit., 66f.; Steinmetz, op. cit., 341. 164 Dox., 181. The question of how precisely these parts corresponded to the 16 (or 18) books of Theophrastus remains open. Chapter 4: The historiographical project of the Lyceum 158 stood by physics, 165 though many of the problems of zoology and botany studied by Aristotle and Theophrastus are lacking here, since the early physi- cists either did not touch upon them at all or paid very little attention to them, which made a representative collection of their opinions impossible. 166 The six parts of Vetusta placita were divided into chapters dealing with in- dividual problems and following each other in logical order. In the part on the soul, e.g., opinions on the five senses in general were duly followed by those on the individual senses: sight, hearing, the sense of smell and taste being taken separately ( Dox., 182). In De sensibus, however, the material is not ar- ranged in accordance with the five senses following in succession, but with the individual thinkers’ theories on all the senses. This reflects Theophrastus’ at- tention not so much to the opinions as such, but rather to the doctrines of con- crete thinkers, in which he tried to emphasize their common as well as individ- ual features. At first, he divides them into two groups: the first follows the prin- ciple ‘like by like’, the second sticks to the opposite principle (1). Individual physicists’ doctrines are then critically exposed according to this division, though not consistently enough. The first group includes the teachings of Par- menides, Plato and Empedocles (3–24), ranged in the order of the growing complexity and elaborateness of their theories ( Dox., 105). Yet they are not fol- lowed by the proponents of the opposite principle, but by all the others, ar- ranged in chronological order: Alcmaeon, Anaxagoras, Clidemus, Diogenes, and Democritus (25–58). 167 The multi-level structure of the Physiko¯n doxai can be preliminarily charac- terized as follows. On the whole, the treatise was organized on systematic prin- ciples, with the choice and the succession of problems reflecting the histori- cally attested interests of the physicists. The material is divided into books 165 According to Theophrastus ( Met. 9a 13–15, 9b 20–10a 4), the subject of physics starts with celestial bodies and ends with animals and plants. Cf. Aët. V, 14. 166 In his writings on plants, Theophrastus repeatedly refers to the Pythagorean Menes- tor, who wrote on the causes of the falling of leaves, on the difference between warm and cold plants, etc. (32 A 2–7). There were no corresponding divisions in the Physi- ko¯n doxai, so that Menestor is lacking here. 167 In section 1, Heraclitus is placed in the second group, but is not mentioned subse- quently. Anaxagoras is the only true representative of the second group, whereas Alcmaeon, Clidemus, Diogenes, and Democritus do not belong entirely to any of them. It seems that the difficulties of clear-cut systematization prompted Theo- phrastus to use the simplest, i.e., chronological, principle. Clidemus’ position be- tween Anaxagoras and Diogenes is the only chronological indication on this obscure figure, on which basis Diels dated him. In the second part of Download 1.41 Mb. Do'stlaringiz bilan baham: |
Ma'lumotlar bazasi mualliflik huquqi bilan himoyalangan ©fayllar.org 2024
ma'muriyatiga murojaat qiling
ma'muriyatiga murojaat qiling