Leonid Zhmud The Origin of the History of Science in Classical Antiquity
Download 1.41 Mb. Pdf ko'rish
|
The Origin of the History of Science in
Elements. In their entirety, the frag-
ments do not cover even one-tenth of the material that – judging by the Cata- logue of geometers in Proclus 12 – was presented in the History of Geometry. Of the twenty mathematicians mentioned in the Catalogue, 13 we find only six in the fragments, including Antiphon, who is omitted from the Catalogue. 14 In reconstructing the original scope of the History of Geometry, we can rely on these fragments as solid ground, yet we cannot confine ourselves solely to them. It is well known that, for the late authors, Eudemus was one of the main sources, if not the main source of information on pre-Euclidean geometry. This does not mean, of course, that any anonymous evidence concerning early Greek mathematics goes back to Eudemus. Nevertheless, there are many cases in which his authorship seems firmly established. Proclus, for example, informs us about two of Thales’ theorems with a reference to Eudemus (fr. 134–135) and about two others without mentioning his name ( In Eucl., 157.10f., 250.20f.). It was suggested long ago that the latter two pieces of evidence are also based on Eudemus’ authority, 15 which seems to me rather obvious. The same conclusion can be reached about two of Oenopides’ discoveries, one of which Proclus mentions with a reference to Eudemus (fr. 138) and the other without it ( In Eucl., 283.7f.). 16 It is also very possible that Eutocius, who cites Archytas’ solution to the problem of doubling the cube with reference to Eude- mus (fr. 141), ultimately owes his information about the solutions of Eudoxus and Menaechmus to the same source. 17 Here is another example: who was the authority for Proclus’ information that the Pythagoreans knew the theorem that only the following polygons can fill up the space around a point: six equilateral triangles, four squares, and three equilateral equiangular hexagons ( In Eucl., 304.11f.)? There is no such theorem in Euclid, but his older contemporary Eudemus could have referred to it, since it follows immediately from the theorem on the equality of the angles of the triangle to two right angles (I, 32), which he ascribes to the Pythago- 11 See also Eudemus’ reference to Hippocrates, omitted by Wehrli: 12 Procl. In Eucl., 64.16–68.23 = Eud. fr. 133. 13 I hesitantly include in this number Philip of Opus, but not Plato; see above, 3.2 and below, 5.3. Hippias of Elis is mentioned here only as a source, not as a mathema- tician. 14 The Catalogue considers those who contributed to the progress of geometry, whereas Antiphon is only known for his unsuccessful attempt to square the circle. 15 Pesch, J.G. van. De Procli fontibus (Diss.), Leiden 1900, 78f.; Heath. Elements I, 36. 16 Van Pesch, ibid.; Heath, ibid. 17 Wehrli, com. ad loc.; Knorr AT, 21. Probably through Eratosthenes, who derives from Eudemus his knowledge of the solutions of Archytas, Eudoxus, and Menaech- mus (3.1). 2. The History of Geometry: on a quest for new evidence 171 reans. 18 It seems very likely that two testimonies from the scholia to Euclid can also be attributed to Eudemus: first, that book IV of the Elements belongs to the Pythagoreans, and second, that they constructed three of the five regular solids (pyramid, cube and dodecahedron), to which Theaetetus added the oc- tahedron and icosahedron. 19 Eudemus, as we know, wrote both on the Pytha- goreans and on Theaetetus; besides, this version contradicts the later erroneous tradition, which ascribed to Pythagoras the construction of all five regular solids (Procl. Download 1.41 Mb. Do'stlaringiz bilan baham: |
Ma'lumotlar bazasi mualliflik huquqi bilan himoyalangan ©fayllar.org 2024
ma'muriyatiga murojaat qiling
ma'muriyatiga murojaat qiling