Leonid Zhmud The Origin of the History of Science in Classical Antiquity
Download 1.41 Mb. Pdf ko'rish
|
The Origin of the History of Science in
pro¯tos heurete¯s principle. Early heurematography
and doxography, Sophistic theories on the origin of culture, Plato’s theory of science, and the expert knowledge of specialists in each of the arts and sciences belong to the most important sources the Lyceum relied on. Yet on the whole, the attempt by Aristotle and his disciples to systematize the entire space of con- 186 Diels, H. Über die Excerpte von Menons Iatrika in dem Londoner Papyrus 137, Hermes 28 (1893) 415, believed that the doxai were arranged by their affinity, yet the systematic order often proved to coincide with the chronological one. 187 Diels (ibid.) was doubtful about Hippon’s and Thrasimachus’ positions; Grensem- ann ( op. cit., 13f.) suggests a different place for Alcamenes; Manetti (op. cit., 118f.) places Plato after Philistion. 188 Diels. Über die Excerpte, 415f.; Manetti, op. cit., 100f. 189 See e.g. the second group (Manetti, op. cit., 119), containing few unfamiliar names: Philolaus – Polybus (a student of Hippocrates) – Menecrates (a doctor of the fourth century) – Petron – Philistion (a contemporary of Plato) – Plato. The first group runs from Euryphon of Cnidus to Aegimius of Aelis, the younger contemporary of Hip- pocrates. 6. Doxography: between systematics and history 165 temporary culture and to give a historical retrospective of its development was unique in Antiquity and found no analogies until the 18 th century. The key notion of Aristotle’s systematics was ëpist2mh, embracing theor- etical sciences, productive arts (music and poetry), and such practical sciences as he was interested in, like politics and rhetoric. Of course, not every historical outline of any of these fields written in the Lyceum was based on the Aristote- lian classification of science, the more so since the latter itself consisted of three different schemes that had emerged at different times: first, the Pythago- rean quadrivium, then the division of sciences into three kinds, and finally the later subdivision of theoretical sciences into mathematics, physics, and theol- ogy. But in the case of the historiographical project, which inquired into the past of all three theoretical sciences (and into medical theories related to physics, as well), the coincidences between Aristotle’s philosophy of science and the history of science written by his disciples are too detailed and numerous to be accidental. Each of these ‘histories’ bore individual features, depending upon the na- ture of the material and the particular task of each treatise. A description of ir- refutable discoveries in mathematics and (partly in) astronomy differed, nat- urally, from that of the contradictory and often erroneous doxai of the physi- cists, which in turn had little in common with a historical overview of ‘prin- ciples’ considered by theologians. Nevertheless, in spite of the predominantly systematic character of the physical and medical doxography, Theophrastus and Meno did their best to build into the very structure of their works the his- torical perspective shared by all the Peripatetics in their approach to accumu- lated scientific knowledge. This perspective is quite clearly reflected in Eude- mus’ works on the history of science. We will turn to these works in the next chapters, drawing parallels from Theophrastus, Meno, and Aristoxenus when necessary. Chapter 5 The history of geometry 1. Eudemus of Rhodes We know little about the founder of the historiography of science Eudemus of Rhodes. Ancient sources depict him as a devoted student of Aristotle, who con- sidered Eudemus (along with Theophrastus) a possible scholarch of the Ly- ceum. 1 We know neither exactly when he was born, nor when he joined Aris- totle’s Lyceum. Eudemus certainly was younger than Theophrastus (born ca. 370), and after Aristotle’s death he returned to Rhodes, where he continued to study and to teach (fr. 88). Eudemus did not lose contact with Theophrastus and corresponded with him on the subject of their teacher’s writings (fr. 6). While Eudemus’ Physics belongs to his Rhodian period, his works on logic and on the history of science were written while Aristotle was still alive. In practically all of the logical fragments, Eudemus figures together with Theo- phrastus, which implies a kind of co-authorship. The list of Theophrastus’ works contains three writings on the history of science with the same titles as Eudemus’ works. 2 Since there are no other traces of such writings in Theo- phrastus, the editors of his fragments subscribed to Usener’s suggestion that these were Eudemus’ works, which were later mistakenly added to Theophras- tus’ list. In the same list we find another work, Tõn perì tò qe$on îstoría~ aV–~V, which, contrary to Wehrli’s opinion, should be identified with Eudemus’ Download 1.41 Mb. Do'stlaringiz bilan baham: |
Ma'lumotlar bazasi mualliflik huquqi bilan himoyalangan ©fayllar.org 2024
ma'muriyatiga murojaat qiling
ma'muriyatiga murojaat qiling