Leonid Zhmud The Origin of the History of Science in Classical Antiquity
parts of the passage indicates that they belong to the same context: Archytas ap-
Download 1.41 Mb. Pdf ko'rish
|
The Origin of the History of Science in
parts of the passage indicates that they belong to the same context: Archytas ap- plied mathematics to mechanics and (mechanical) motion to mathematics. 42 Let us recall that Eudemus wrote on Archytas both in the History of Geometry and in the Physics, where he states that Archytas considered things unequal (tò Ánison) and uneven (tò @nømalon) to be causes of motion (fr. 60, cf. fr. 65). Krafft connected this idea with the principle of the unequal concentric circles, the main principle of motion in the Aristotelian Mechanical Problems, and con- cluded that it derives from Archytas’ mechanics. 43 Hence, Eudemus must have known Archytas’ work in mechanics, which indirectly confirms his authority in Diogenes Laertius’ passage. It is Eudemus’ evidence again that seems to be the source of the passage from Archimedes’ Quadrature of the Parabola, where he refers to the geo- meters who tried to square a circle but, according to most experts’ opinions, failed to do this. 44 He clearly means here the attempts of Hippocrates, Anti- 38 The translation according to Kühn’s conjecture, maqhmatika$~ @rca$~. 39 Fr. 66 Mensching = 47 A 10a. The passages in Diogenes Laertius, where he enumer- ates one eÛrhma after another, usually derive from Favorinus. In his Manifold His- tory there was a special book on pro¯toi heuretai. See Mensching, op. cit., 31f., 161 (index on the word prõto~). 40 Cf. fr. 27 Mensching (Eratosthenes as a source). 41 Eutoc. In Archim. De sphaer., 96.6f. 42 kínhsi~ örganik2 does not mean, however, that Archytas solved the problem using some mechanical device, as Plutarch suggested ( Quaest. conv. 718 E: örganikaì kaì mhcanikaì kataskeuaí). It might probably refer to the movement generated by the rotation of geometrical figures and bodies. 43 See above, 97 n. 82–83. 44 dióper aÿto$~ ûpò tõn pleístwn oÿc eûriskómena tañta kategnwsqén (II, 263.19–264.1). 2. The History of Geometry: on a quest for new evidence 177 phon, and Bryson to square a circle, which Aristotle briefly mentioned 45 and Eudemus treated more extensively (fr. 139–140; but he passes over Bryson in silence). Since Eudemus, in contrast to Aristotle, used to support his judgments by presenting the corresponding geometrical constructions, he was almost surely implied among the experts to whom Archimedes alluded. The following example is less obvious, but no less interesting. In the intro- duction to his Method Archimedes writes: In the case of the theorems, the proof of which Eudoxus was first to discover, namely, that the cone is a third part of the cylinder, and the pyramid of the prism, having the same base and equal height, we should give no small share of credit to Democritus, who was the first to make an assertion with regard to the said figure, though he did not prove it. 46 Archimedes refers to Democritus only once and hardly knew his works. Eu- doxus, it seems, does not mention Democritus either. This follows from the in- troduction to Archimedes’ treatise On the Sphere and Cylinder, written before the Method, where he refers to the same discoveries of Eudoxus, adding that before him no geometer came to these ideas (I, 4.5f. = fr. 62b Lasserre). Thus, at that time, Archimedes did not know of any of Eudoxus’ predecessors in this field. Later, in the Method, he corrects his view, but was this correction due to his acquaintance with Democritus’ books? The following prompts us rather to suppose that Archimedes took the comparison of Eudoxus and Democritus from Eudemus’ Download 1.41 Mb. Do'stlaringiz bilan baham: |
Ma'lumotlar bazasi mualliflik huquqi bilan himoyalangan ©fayllar.org 2024
ma'muriyatiga murojaat qiling
ma'muriyatiga murojaat qiling