Leonid Zhmud The Origin of the History of Science in Classical Antiquity


parts of the passage indicates that they belong to the same context: Archytas ap-


Download 1.41 Mb.
Pdf ko'rish
bet140/261
Sana08.05.2023
Hajmi1.41 Mb.
#1444838
1   ...   136   137   138   139   140   141   142   143   ...   261
Bog'liq
The Origin of the History of Science in


parts of the passage indicates that they belong to the same context: Archytas ap-
plied mathematics to mechanics and (mechanical) motion to mathematics.
42
Let us recall that Eudemus wrote on Archytas both in the
History of Geometry
and in the
Physics, where he states that Archytas considered things unequal (tò
Ánison) and uneven (tò @nømalon) to be causes of motion (fr. 60, cf. fr. 65).
Krafft connected this idea with the principle of the unequal concentric circles,
the main principle of motion in the Aristotelian
Mechanical Problems, and con-
cluded that it derives from Archytas’ mechanics.
43
Hence, Eudemus must have
known Archytas’ work in mechanics, which indirectly confirms his authority in
Diogenes Laertius’ passage.
It is Eudemus’ evidence again that seems to be the source of the passage
from Archimedes’
Quadrature of the Parabola, where he refers to the geo-
meters who tried to square a circle but, according to most experts’ opinions,
failed to do this.
44
He clearly means here the attempts of Hippocrates, Anti-
38
The translation according to Kühn’s conjecture, maqhmatika$~ @rca$~.
39
Fr. 66 Mensching = 47 A 10a. The passages in Diogenes Laertius, where he enumer-
ates one eÛrhma after another, usually derive from Favorinus. In his Manifold His-
tory there was a special book on pro¯toi heuretai. See Mensching, op. cit., 31f., 161
(index on the word prõto~).
40
Cf. fr. 27 Mensching (Eratosthenes as a source).
41
Eutoc.
In Archim. De sphaer., 96.6f.
42
kínhsi~ örganik2 does not mean, however, that Archytas solved the problem using
some mechanical device, as Plutarch suggested (
Quaest. conv. 718 E: örganikaì
kaì mhcanikaì kataskeuaí). It might probably refer to the movement generated by
the rotation of geometrical figures and bodies.
43
See above, 97 n. 82–83.
44
dióper aÿto$~ ûpò tõn pleístwn oÿc eûriskómena tañta kategnwsqén (II,
263.19–264.1).


2.
The History of Geometry: on a quest for new evidence
177
phon, and Bryson to square a circle, which Aristotle briefly mentioned
45
and
Eudemus treated more extensively (fr. 139–140; but he passes over Bryson in
silence). Since Eudemus, in contrast to Aristotle, used to support his judgments
by presenting the corresponding geometrical constructions, he was almost
surely implied among the experts to whom Archimedes alluded.
The following example is less obvious, but no less interesting. In the intro-
duction to his
Method Archimedes writes:
In the case of the theorems, the proof of which Eudoxus was first to discover,
namely, that the cone is a third part of the cylinder, and the pyramid of the prism,
having the same base and equal height, we should give no small share of credit to
Democritus, who was the first to make an assertion with regard to the said figure,
though he did not prove it.
46
Archimedes refers to Democritus only once and hardly knew his works. Eu-
doxus, it seems, does not mention Democritus either. This follows from the in-
troduction to Archimedes’ treatise
On the Sphere and Cylinder, written before
the
Method, where he refers to the same discoveries of Eudoxus, adding that
before him no geometer came to these ideas (I, 4.5f. = fr. 62b Lasserre). Thus,
at that time, Archimedes did not know of any of Eudoxus’ predecessors in this
field. Later, in the
Method, he corrects his view, but was this correction due to
his acquaintance with Democritus’ books? The following prompts us rather to
suppose that Archimedes took the comparison of Eudoxus and Democritus
from Eudemus’

Download 1.41 Mb.

Do'stlaringiz bilan baham:
1   ...   136   137   138   139   140   141   142   143   ...   261




Ma'lumotlar bazasi mualliflik huquqi bilan himoyalangan ©fayllar.org 2024
ma'muriyatiga murojaat qiling