Leonid Zhmud The Origin of the History of Science in Classical Antiquity
Download 1.41 Mb. Pdf ko'rish
|
The Origin of the History of Science in
APo 75b 37f.;
SE 171b 15f., 172a 3f.). Later Aristotle’s commentators discussed it (Heath. Mathe- matics, 47f.; Mueller. Aristotle, 160ff.; Knorr. AT, 76f.), but they, it seems, had no sources apart from Aristotle. That means that Eudemus, while reporting Antiphon’s attempts, fails to mention Bryson. Whatever Eudemus’ motives could have been, Bryson was certainly not a mathematician. 51 In Eucl., 77.16, 202.11, 220.9, 254.4; cf. van Pesch, op. cit., 112f. On Geminus, see below, 184f., 291f. 52 See Bowen. Menaechmus, 14f.; Knorr. AT, 74f. 53 Cf. Tannery. Géométrie, 138 n. 1. Knorr. AT, 74f. and Tarán. Proclus, 238 n. 37, are indecisive about Amphinomus’ chronology; Lasserre included him in the list of the ‘Academic mathematicians’ ( Léodamas, 149f., 587f.). 3. The Catalogue of geometers: from Eudemus to Proclus 179 are otherwise unknown; Oenopides of Chios was the older contemporary of Hippocrates. But was he the Oenopides that Geminus had in mind? Geminus discusses the distinction between theorems and problems; their definitions given by Zenodotus are very close to those of Posidonius’ followers (80.15f.). Thus, in all probability, Oenopides, Zenodotus, and Andron also belong to the Hellenistic period. 54 The chronology of Aristeas the Elder, who wrote on conic sections and regu- lar solids (Pappus and Eutocius mention him), is still uncertain. 55 In any case, he was younger than Menaechmus, who discovered the conic sections and probably belonged to Euclid’s generation. 56 3. The Catalogue of geometers: from Eudemus to Proclus Moving from the evident cases to the less evident, we come to one of our cen- tral problems: who was the author of the Catalogue of geometers and how did this document come to Proclus? It was customary since the late 19 th century to think of the information in the Catalogue as going back, albeit through inter- mediaries, to Eudemus’ History of Geometry (fr. 133). 57 Although Proclus does 54 Knorr. AT, 374 n. 70, cf. Bowen. Menaechmus, 13f. Since Geminus’ methodological discussion of theorems and problems is based on Posidonius ( In Eucl., 77.7–78.10, 80.15–81.4 = fr. 195 E.-K.), the other references to Amphinomus, Speusippus, Me- naechmus, Oenopides, Zenodotus, and Andron might derive from the same source. Aëtius (I,7.17) mentions Oenopides along with the Stoics Diogenes and Cleanthes, and a Stoic idea, the god is the soul of the world, is ascribed to him (see below, 7.5). Von Fritz. Oinopides, 2267f., was wrong to relate the methodological discussion on theorems and problems to Oenopides of Chios: it could not have taken place in the fifth century. 55 Allman, op. cit., 194ff.; Heath, T. L. Apollonius of Perga, Cambridge 1896, xxiff; Knorr, W. R. Observations on the early history of the conics, Centaurus 26 (1982) 1–24; idem. AT, 32f.; Pappus of Alexandria. Book 7 of the Collection, transl. by A. Jones, Pt. 2, New York 1986, 404, 577f. 56 More complicated is the case of the mathematician Thymaridas. Iamblichus ( In Nicom., 11.2f., 27.4, 62.19, 65.9, 68.3f. = Timpanaro Cardini, M. Pitagorici – Tes- timonianze e frammenti, Pt. 2, Florence 1962, 444f.) quotes his definition of a number and an arithmetic puzzle, the so-called epanthem. Since a certain Thymari- das of Paros is named in the catalogue of the Pythagoreans compiled by Aristoxenus ( Download 1.41 Mb. Do'stlaringiz bilan baham: |
Ma'lumotlar bazasi mualliflik huquqi bilan himoyalangan ©fayllar.org 2024
ma'muriyatiga murojaat qiling
ma'muriyatiga murojaat qiling