Leonid Zhmud The Origin of the History of Science in Classical Antiquity
Download 1.41 Mb. Pdf ko'rish
|
The Origin of the History of Science in
ximandre. Fragments et témoignages, Paris 1991, 203 n. 23. Cf. Arist. Cael. 295b
11–16: in Anaximander, the earth is at rest. 81 “Eudemus is trying to discover, in a good Aristotelian fashion, the nature of progress in science that led to the situation as he knew it; results are what he wants to record.” (Burkert. L & S, 308). 2. Thales and Anaximander 247 column’s drum. To be sure, the few extant fragments of the History of Astron- omy, even when supplemented by parallel material from the History of Ge- ometry, do not enable us to say how consistently Eudemus discarded erroneous ideas. It would be rash to allege that all the ideas that contradicted the views of the fourth-century specialists in astronomy remained outside the History of As- tronomy. By its very nature, astronomy could not develop as victoriously as mathematics, and since even in the History of Geometry there is criticism of Antiphon’s failed attempt to square a circle, we can expect the History of As- tronomy to have contained similar material as well. In Antiphon’s case, how- ever, ‘failed’ means ‘an attempt made by non-mathematical methods’, whereas astronomy’s criteria of truth were not as strict as those used in geometry. Even Eudoxian theory, the most scientific of the day, failed to ‘save the phenomena’ adequately and required further modifications. Hence, one can readily surmise that Eudemus, when sorting out the discoveries of the ancient astronomers, was compelled to apply less strict standards than those used in the History of Geometry. These considerations are supported by the testimony already cited: Anaxi- mander was the first to find an account of the sizes and distances of heavenly bodies (fr. 146). 82 What is instructive here are the words prõtou … tòn lógon eûrhkóto~. 83 Eudemus could not assert that Anaximander was the first to have found the true sizes of heavenly bodies and the actual distances be- tween them: the figures accepted at the end of the fourth century differed con- siderably from those of Anaximander, 84 not to mention that his system placed 82 Further on, Simplicius notes that the size of the sun and the moon and their distances from the earth are estimated by observing eclipses ( In Cael. comm., 471.6–8). His suggestion that this method was also discovered by Anaximander is, of course, er- roneous: such computations appeared in the third century BC. 83 Mansfeld, J. Cosmic distances: Aëtius 2. 31 Diels and some related texts, Le style de la pensée. Recueil de textes en hommage à J. Brunschwig, ed. by M. Canto-Sperber, P. Pellegrin, Paris 2002, 429–463, translates this phrase first as “Anaximander was first to discover the ratio (lógo~) of the sizes and of the distances”, but then as “An- aximander was first to speak of the sizes and distances” (454, 459). Now, lógo~ perì megeqõn kaì @posthmátwn cannot possibly mean ‘ratio’, either in Eudemus, or in Simplicius; in the latter lógo~ perí normally means ‘a theory/explanation of’. Hence, Mansfeld’s assertion, built solely on his first translation, that the doxographi- cal information on the sizes and distances in Anaximander derives from Eudemus, and not from Theophrastus, remains unsubstantiated. 84 In Anaximander, the sun is of the same size as the earth (12 A 21); Philip of Opus ( Epin. 983a) and Aristotle (Mete. 345a 36) believed it to be greater than the earth. Eudoxus considered the sun to be 9 times greater than the moon (D 13 Lasserre) and (possibly) 3.3 times greater than the earth (Heath. Download 1.41 Mb. Do'stlaringiz bilan baham: |
Ma'lumotlar bazasi mualliflik huquqi bilan himoyalangan ©fayllar.org 2024
ma'muriyatiga murojaat qiling
ma'muriyatiga murojaat qiling