Book · January 994 citations 110 reads 2,264 authors
Download 5.72 Mb. Pdf ko'rish
|
1994 Book DidacticsOfMathematicsAsAScien
Didactics of Mathematics as a Scientific Discipline, 103-116.
© 1994 Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic Publishers. Printed in the Netherlands. 1. INTRODUCTION In this chapter, I will raise the issue of what it means to be scientific in the context of conducting research on teaching and teacher education. I will ar- gue that our notion of being scientific is related to how we see change evolving in the teaching and learning of mathematics. The concepts of au- thority and adaptation will be considered as they are related to teacher edu- cation. the latest educational fad is even worse. (Brophy, 1975, p. 15) While the debate raged in the 1970s over the applicability of science to the art of teaching, what was obscured was the question of what constitutes sci- ence. A review of published research in the United States during this period suggests a view of science as an exercise in yielding statistical generaliza- tions. Most of this research involved the process/product paradigm in which teacher behaviors were correlated with achievement – usually defined in terms of basic skills (see, e.g., Rosenshine & Furst, 1973). In the main, this research had little impact on the field of mathematics education. By the late 1970s, the field was beginning to turn its head. Researchers, at least in the United States, began to study teachers' decision-making pro- cesses, thereby giving the impression that the questions were more cogni- tively oriented, yet holding tightly to the notion of "traditional" science. A study by Peterson and Clark (1978) is illustrative, as they traced the nature and types of decisions teachers made using correlational analyses. But there were other voices being heard, some inside and some outside the field of mathematics education, that raised more fundamental issues. From a methodological perspective, Mitroff and Kilmann (1978) concluded that "science is in serious need of methodological and epistemological reform" (p. 30). The authors maintained that "Even if there were no 'crises of belief ' in science, there would still be good reasons for considering reform at this time, given the new cultural forces and streams of thought being articulated" (p. 3). Mitroff and Kilmann's (1978) analysis led them to identify four types of scientist. One type, the analytic scientist, believes in the value-free nature of science, that is, knowledge is separable from values. In contrast, the au- thors identified two other types, the conceptual humanist and the particular humanist, who focus on descriptions of human activity, raising the question of whether stories are an appropriate mechanism for communicating re- search findings. Perhaps the most serious attack on the notion of "traditional science" came from Feyerabend (1988) who maintained that "the events, procedures, and results that constitute the sciences have no common structure" (p. 1). Feyerabend's (1988) orientation toward science supports an eclectic view of the way science should be conducted. According to Feyerabend, science, as defined by an allegiance to regimented procedures, runs the risk of under- mining the value gained from human ingenuity, insight, and compassion. Similarly, Mitroff and Kilmann (1978) observed that, "The greatest scien- tists seem not only to combine the attributes of opposing types but to delight in doing so" (p. 12). At one level, we can say that research on teaching has moved from what teachers were (i.e., their characteristics) in the 1950s and 1960s, to what teachers did in the 1970s, to what teachers decided in the early 1980s, to the more recent focus on what teachers believe (see Brown, Cooney, & Jones, 1990; Thompson, 1992). Such an analysis would miss, however, what was 104 SCIENCE AND TEACHER EDUCATION happening conceptually and methodologically in mathematics education. With the emerging prominence of the constructivist epistemology (in its many forms), a premium has been placed on meaning and context. This em- phasis challenges us to reconsider what we mean by being scientific, includ- ing the notion of being objective. Von Glasersfeld addresses the issue of ob- jectivity in the following way: In order to observe anything, in order to "collect data," one must have some no- tion – no matter how primitive and preliminary – of the particular experiences one intends to relate to one another. It is, obviously, these experiences that one will be looking for. In order to find them, one necessarily assimilates and disregards all sorts of differences in individual observations. The longer this goes on successfully and the more often the model one has constructed proves useful, the stronger becomes the belief that one has discovered a real connection, if not a Download 5.72 Mb. Do'stlaringiz bilan baham: |
Ma'lumotlar bazasi mualliflik huquqi bilan himoyalangan ©fayllar.org 2024
ma'muriyatiga murojaat qiling
ma'muriyatiga murojaat qiling