Leonid Zhmud The Origin of the History of Science in Classical Antiquity
Download 1.41 Mb. Pdf ko'rish
|
The Origin of the History of Science in
similar, not equal;
3) was the first to discover that if two straight lines cut one another, the vertical angles are equal (I, 15), whereas the scientific proof for this theorem was given later by Euclid, as Proclus adds; and 4) knew the theorem about the equality of the triangles that have one side and two angles equal (I, 26), which he must have used to determine the distances of ships from the shore. 110 Did Thales really need to go Egypt to learn there that the diameter divides the circle in half? On the other hand, his theorems concerning angles and triangles are not in the least related to Egyptian mathematics, which was never preoccupied with comparing angles and establishing the similarity of triangles. 111 In fact, Egyptian geometry lacked the notion of an angle as a measurable quantity – it was, in this respect, ‘linear’, unlike the ‘angle’ geometry of the Greeks, in which angles first be- came objects of measurement. 112 The statement that the diameter divides the circle in half is not proved in Eu- clid, but accepted as a definition. Thales, in his demonstration, must have re- sorted to the method of superposition, 113 which in early Greek geometry was employed much more often than in the time of Eudemus and Euclid. As von Fritz observed, All theorems ascribed to Thales are either directly related to the problems of sym- metry and can be ‘demonstrated’ by the method of superposition, or such that the first step of the demonstration is evidently based on considerations of symmetry while the second, which brings the argument to conclusion, is simply an addition or subtraction. 114 In the fourth century, mathematicians tried to avoid this visual and overly em- pirical method. It is still to be found, however, in some theorems from Euclid’s book I (4, 8). When saying that Thales treated certain things in geometry more empirically (aısqhtikøteron), Eudemus could well have meant the method of superposition. It does not follow, however, that Thales appealed in his demon- strations to nothing but the visualizability of the geometrical drawing. In the case of I, 5 we are able to verify this claim: there is a proof of this theorem in Aristotle that is different from the one found in Euclid and might well go back to Thales. 115 It is based on the equality of mixed angles – the angles of a semi- circle and the angles of a circular segment, in particular – which, in turn, could only be demonstrated by superposition or follow from the definition of such angles. The proof proceeds in the following way: 110 Fr. 134–135, Procl. In Eucl., 157.10f., 250.20f. 111 Vogel, K. Vorgriechische Mathematik, Hannover 1958–1959, Pt. 1, 72; Pt. 2, 23 n. 2, 39 n. 4. 112 Gands, S. The origin of angle-geometry, Isis 12 (1929) 452–482. 113 Heath. Elements 1, 225; von Fritz. Grundprobleme, 401ff., 477f. 114 Von Fritz. Grundprobleme, 568 n. 79. 115 APr 41b 13–22. See Heath. Elements 1, 252f.; von Fritz. Grundprobleme, 475f.; Neuenschwander. VB, 358f. 4. Early Greek geometry according to Eudemus 193 ABC is an isosceles triangle with the apex in the center of a circle. Prove that the angles at the base are equal. ∠ 1 = ∠ 2 since both of them are angles of the semicircle. ∠ 3 = ∠ 4 since two angles of any segment are equal to each other. Subtracting equal angles 3 and 4 from equal angles 1 and 2, we obtain that angles CAB and CBA are equal to each other. The proof in Aristotle derives most probably from the Elements by Leon or Theudius, whereas Eudemus’ source must have retained Thales’ archaic termi- nology (Ômoioi instead of Ísoi). The theorem on the equality of vertical angles (I, 15) could also have been proved by the method of superposition. Euclid gives a different demonstration of this theorem, based on I, 13. According to Neuenschwander’s reconstruc- tion, I, 13–15 in their present form entered the Elements either in the time of Eu- clid or shortly before him. 116 That fully agrees with Proclus’ remark that the scientific proof of I, 15 belongs to Euclid. Proclus (or his source) could have come to this conclusion by comparing the proof of Thales cited by Eudemus with Euclid’s proof, which was, naturally, more rigorous. Unlike the first three, Thales’ fourth theorem is ascribed to him by Eudemus on the force of an indirect argument: the method Thales used to determine the distances of ships from the shore presupposes the use of this theorem. Without going into the details of different reconstructions of this method, 117 we note that Eudemus used his sources with discrimination and was perfectly able to distin- guish between what was passed on directly by the tradition, on the one hand, and his personal conjectures and hypotheses, on the other. The fact that here we might be dealing with a mere reconstruction, possibly a fallacious one, 118 does not cast doubt on other things we learn from Eudemus about Thales – no history of mathematics can dispense with reconstructions. Numerous attempts to cast doubt on the facts Eudemus reports, and, along with them, Thales’ place in the history of Greek geometry have so far all proved futile. 119 The information re- 116 Neuenschwander. VB, 361f. 117 The most convincing one is suggested by Heath. History 1, 131f., cf. van der Waerden. EW, 144f. 118 Gigon. Ursprung, 55, supposed that the method of calculating the distance to a ship at sea derives from the Nautical Astronomy, ascribed to Thales (11 B 1). But this work was written in verse and so hardly suitable for the exposition of geometrical proofs. The practical value of this method for navigation is doubtful as well. 119 See von Fritz’s detailed answer ( Grundprobleme, 337ff.) on doubts expressed by K. Reidemeister ( Das exakte Denken der Griechen, Hamburg 1949, 18ff.) and Neugebauer ( ES, 142). The hypercritical position of D. R. Dicks (Thales, CQ 9 [1959] 294–309, esp. 301f.) is not convincing; cf. Zaicev. Griechisches Wunder, 210f. Chapter 5: The history of geometry 194 ported by Eudemus is rich and accurate and includes details that could not have been invented; the theorems he attributes to Thales show close mutual intercon- nection. 120 Even if we cannot identify the source of Eudemus’ information on Thales’ geometry, this only means that he had at his disposal certain texts that are inaccessible to us. 121 About Mamercus, the next geometer after Thales, Eudemus must have only known the little he learned from Hippias ( In Eucl., 64.11f.). Judging by the general context in Hippias’ Collection, investigated by A. Patzer, this reference was hardly isolated. Most likely, Mamercus was named along with the other fa- mous geometers of his time, Thales and Pythagoras. This suggestion seems the more probable since, in the early doxography, Hippias played an important role as a transmitter of evidence about Thales. Though Patzer himself believed that geometry also belongs to the circle of themes examined by Hippias, 122 his own reconstruction of the Collection leaves little room to suppose that it contained Download 1.41 Mb. Do'stlaringiz bilan baham: |
Ma'lumotlar bazasi mualliflik huquqi bilan himoyalangan ©fayllar.org 2024
ma'muriyatiga murojaat qiling
ma'muriyatiga murojaat qiling