Leonid Zhmud The Origin of the History of Science in Classical Antiquity
Download 1.41 Mb. Pdf ko'rish
|
The Origin of the History of Science in
Léodamas, 552f.), who never-
theless saw the ultimate source in Philip’s book On Plato (cf. above, 89f.). 206 I shall treat this subject in a forthcoming paper “On two Menaechmi”. As a prelimi- nary, it is worth pointing out that we find in Geminus quite a few other ‘doubles’. 1) The Theodorus attested by Geminus (Procl. In Eucl., 118.7) is definitely not Theodorus of Cyrene, but a Hellenistic mathematician; 2) the Oenopides to whose ‘succession’ Zenodotus belonged (ibid., 85.15f.) is not Oenopides of Chios, but most likely a Stoic philosopher (see above, 179 n. 54, and below, 260 n. 134); 3) the Hippias who found the quadratrix (ibid., 272.8f., 356.6f.) is not the famous Sophist Hippias, but a Hellenistic mathematician (Knorr. AT, 82f.). 207 See above, 98f. 208 Translation according to Grynaeus’ conjecture merikõn instead of the manuscript ôrikõn. 209 Knorr. AT, 142 n. 30, 371 n. 25. Chapter 5: The history of geometry 210 5. Teleological progressivism Generally, Eudemus paid attention not only to the results and the form of their exposition, but also to the method of the proof and its correspondence to what was customary in his own time. In the Catalogue, the improvement of geo- metrical methods is discussed in much detail. Thales’ method is characterized as in some cases more empirical, and in others more general, i.e., scientific, whereas Pythagoras is credited with transforming geometry into an abstract science and including it in the canon of education of a free man. Owing to the efforts of Leodamas, Archytas, and Theaetetus, geometry became “more scien- tific and systematic”, Leon discovered the method of diorism, and Eudoxus used the method of analysis, while Amyclas, Menaechmus, and Dinostratus “made the whole of geometry even more perfect” (Éti telewtéran ëpoíhsan t3n Ôlhn gewmetrían, 67.11). It is significant that the Catalogue starts with the words about progressing “from the imperfect to the perfect” (@pò toñ @teloñ~ eı~ tò téleion, 64.25) and ends with the notice that “those who com- piled histories of geometry bring the perfecting (teleíwsi~) of geometry up to this point” (68.4f.). Of course, no author who lived after Eudemus could have the idea of the ‘completion’ of geometry at the end of the fourth century, i.e., before Euclid, Archimedes, and Apollonius. This confirms again that the begin- ning of the Catalogue, as well, goes back to Eudemus. I have suggested above that, in his histories of the exact sciences, Eudemus employed the professional approach – of course, to the extent that this was possible for a Peripatetic philosopher. This does not contradict the fact that Eudemus’ views on development in general, and on the development of science in particular, rely on the Aristotelian doctrine that we call teleological progres- sivism. According to this doctrine, everything in nature, society, and culture de- velops from a primitive state to a perfect one, 210 and for many things this state of perfection was thought to have already been achieved or almost achieved. Tragedy, for example, had already attained its perfection, society had found its best and final state in the polis, and philosophy, whose early ideas were as im- mature as childish speech, would be soon completed. 211 Against this back- ground, Eudemus’ idea that geometry had achieved or almost achieved perfec- tion seems quite natural. 212 To be sure, such progressivism (not necessarily a teleological one) was characteristic not only of Aristotle, but of many other 210 “There is evolution towards a state of excellence all over in the design of nature; the goal is the end, Download 1.41 Mb. Do'stlaringiz bilan baham: |
Ma'lumotlar bazasi mualliflik huquqi bilan himoyalangan ©fayllar.org 2024
ma'muriyatiga murojaat qiling
ma'muriyatiga murojaat qiling