Leonid Zhmud The Origin of the History of Science in Classical Antiquity
Download 1.41 Mb. Pdf ko'rish
|
The Origin of the History of Science in
Ethics (981b 26f.).
217 Democritus (68 B 144) says nothing about leisure. The first to mention leisure was Isocrates ( Bus. 21–23), followed by Plato (Crit. 110a). But leisure plays no role in the Laws (677a–683b), where Plato’s theory on the origin of culture is stated in great detail, or in the Epinomis (974d 3–977b 8). 218 See e.g. fr. 53 Rose = Protr. fr. 8 Ross; Pol. 1329b 25f., where leisure is not men- tioned. 219 Met. 981a 12 f., 981b 10 f.; EN 1139a 17f. See also Wehrli’s commentary on fr. 133. Chapter 5: The history of geometry 212 scheme, Eudemus emphasized the practical origin of Egyptian geometry, since even Thales, who borrowed this science from Egypt, still proved some things in a more particular and some in a more general way (fr. 133). The idea of the progressive growth of knowledge is older than both Aristotle and Eudemus. Already Isocrates employs ëpídosi~ and ëpididónai as notions designating qualitative development and advancement ( Paneg. 10, 103, 189). The verbs from the same semantic group, such as aÿxánein, proagage$n, and proércesqai, acquire a similar meaning with Isocrates. 220 These notions are often found where he discusses the discovery and development of various téc- nai, in particular the progress of rhetoric and the constant quest for novelties. 221 Aristotle employs the verb proagage$n when referring to the advancement of mathematics by the Pythagoreans ( Met. 985b 23f.) and ëpídosi~ for express- ing the idea of rapid progress in contemporary mathematics and in all the téc- nai in general (EN 1098a 24–25). In Philodemus’ quotation from the Aca- demic treatise, ëpídosi~ is used twice: first, with regard to all mathematical sciences, and second, in connection with geometry. In Eudemus, ëpídosi~ ap- pears only once, and conspicuously in the passage of the Catalogue praising Plato’s role in geometry, but aÿxánein, proagage$n, proércesqai occur in this text unusually often. 222 One of the criteria of progress in mathematics, for Eudemus, was the degree of generality of mathematical propositions. 223 Thales was the first to teach ge- ometry “more generally” ( In Eucl., 65.10), Eudoxus augmented the number of “general theorems” (67.4) by developing a new theory of proportions, and Theudius gave to many partial propositions a more general character (67.15). This also coincides with Aristotle’s notion of the development of sciences from the particular to the general. Another notion shared by the Peripatetics was the idea, going back to Plato, of the cyclical character of the historical process. 224 Humankind, being eternal, periodically goes through a number of regional ca- tastrophes in which most arts and sciences perish, so that later generations are compelled to discover everything (or nearly everything) anew. 225 Proclus refers to Aristotle’s opinion on the periodical emergence of sciences before the very beginning of the Catalogue (64.8f.), which, in Wehrli’s edition, opens with the 220 See above, 77 n. 140. 221 See e.g. Nic. 32, Antid. 81–83, 185, Paneg. 10. 222 ëpauxánein (66.16), aÿxánein (67.5), proagage$n (67.7, 67.22), proércesqai (66.17). See Edelstein, op. cit., 92; Thraede. Fortschritt, 141f., 154. 223 Lasserre. Eudoxos, 161f. 224 See above, 109 n. 133. 225 Arist. fr. 13 Rose (= fr. 463 Gigon), fr. 53 (= Protr. fr. 8 Ross = fr. 74.1 Gigon); Cael. 270b 16–24; Mete. 339b 25–30; Met. 1074b 10–13; Pol. 1269a 5f., 1329b 25–33; Theophr. fr. 184 FHSG; Dicaearch. fr. 24. Cf. oÿ gàr mónon pólei~ te kaì Éqnh, fhsín, @rcà~ kaì télh lambánousin, !~ eı~ pantel4 l2qhn ëkpese$n, @llà kaì dóxai kaì técnai kaì ëpist4mai toñto páscousin (Philop. In Arist. Mete., 17.26f.). See Festugière. Révélation, 219f.; Palmer, op. cit., 192ff., 196 n. 26. 5. Teleological progressivism 213 following words: “Since we have to examine the beginnings of arts and sci- ences in the course of the present period …”. 226 Uncertain as we are whether these words go back to Eudemus himself, the idea formulated here is quite ap- propriate for an introduction to the History of Geometry. In his Physics, Eude- mus criticized the Pythagorean idea of recurrence of all phenomena and events in exactly the same way (@riqmŒ, fr. 88), but this is obviously not what the Ar- istotelian theory implies. Defending this theory, Theophrastus stated that the discoverers of sciences had lived about a thousand years earlier (fr. 184.145f. FHSG), which brings us back to the period immediately preceding the Trojan War, the period with which the Greeks used to start the history of their cul- ture. 227 There is no reason to suppose that Eudemus rejected the idea of the cyc- lical development of sciences, especially since in all other cases the coinciding or at least the proximity of the basic historical notions of the teacher and the student are obvious. Hence, it is Aristotle’s historico-philosophical notions of the development of humankind in general and of arts and sciences in particular that formed the conceptual basis of the History of Geometry. That is what distinguished Eude- mus’ history from the ordinary histories that, according to Aristotle, describe a great number of events coinciding in time but having no connection with each other ( Poet. 1459a 16–29). 228 Unlike them, Eudemus’ îstoría contains, in compliance with Aristotle’s requirements, both @rc2 and télo~, and possesses an intrinsic unity as a result. The events of this history, i.e., the discoveries of Greek mathematicians, were connected by causal relationship, which Eudemus never failed to emphasize, and demonstrated, in total, the general regularities in the progressive growth of knowledge: from the simple to the complex, from the Download 1.41 Mb. Do'stlaringiz bilan baham: |
Ma'lumotlar bazasi mualliflik huquqi bilan himoyalangan ©fayllar.org 2024
ma'muriyatiga murojaat qiling
ma'muriyatiga murojaat qiling