Leonid Zhmud The Origin of the History of Science in Classical Antiquity
Download 1.41 Mb. Pdf ko'rish
|
The Origin of the History of Science in
Elements.
187 As for the method of diorism, though the Academic work relates its discovery to the mid-fourth century, we have good reason to suppose that it had been used earlier. 188 It is possible that Leon formulated the method clearly or improved it, rather than invented it. Much more detailed is the information Eudemus provides on Eudoxus. Ac- cording to the Catalogue, Eudoxus 1) “was the first to increase the number of the so-called general theorems”, 2) added three new proportionals to the three already known, and 3) “multiplied the theorems concerning the section …, 183 See Heath. History 1, 246ff.; Becker. Denken, 76f.; van der Waerden. EW, 150f.; Böker, op. cit., 1203f.; Knorr. AT, 50f. 184 Neuenschwander, E. Zur Überlieferung der Archytas-Lösung des delischen Prob- lems, Centaurus 18 (1974) 1–5; Knorr. AT, 50f.; idem. TS, 100ff. It does not mean that the History of Geometry was inaccessible to Eutocius: he refers to it in another work ( In Archim. De dimens. circ., 228.20 = Eud. fr. 139). Like Simplicius, he could have quoted Eudemus at second hand as well, if it was convenient for him. Knorr. TS, 100ff., suggested Geminus or Sporus as possible intermediaries between them, but there is no evidence that Geminus used Eudemus (see above, 184 f.). 185 See above, 176f. 186 See above, 173ff. 187 Lasserre. Birth, 18. 188 Heath. History 1, 319f.; Lasserre. Léodamas, 516f. This method can be clearly traced, in particular, in Plato’s Meno, written ca. 385. See Knorr. AT, 73f.; Menn, S. Plato and the method of analysis, Phronesis 47 (2002) 193–223. 4. Early Greek geometry according to Eudemus 207 employing the method of analysis for their solution”. 189 To this one should add: 4) the information from the scholia that Eudoxus was the author of book V of the Elements, containing the general theory of proportions, 5) Eratos- thenes’ and Eutocius’ evidence on Eudoxus’ solution to the problem of doubl- ing the cube, and, finally, 6) the words of Archimedes that Eudoxus proved the theorem that each cone equals one-third of the cylinder and every pyramid equals one-third of the prism with the same base and height. 190 Nos. 1 and 4 refer, it seems, to one and the same discovery, namely, to the general theory of proportions. This, in any case, is how “the so-called general theorems” (tà kaloúmena kaqólou qewr2mata) are usually understood. 191 Similar ex- pressions occurring in Aristotle (1 kaqólou maqhmatik2 and tà kaqólou ën ta$~ maq2masin), are normally interpreted as a reference to Eudoxus’ the- ory of proportions applied equally to all magnitudes (numbers, lines, figures, etc.). 192 By contrast, the “theorems concerning the section” (tà perì t3n tom3n), whose number Eudoxus multiplied, applying to them the method of analysis, remain obscure. Lasserre, following Bretschneider, was inclined to relate them to the section of line in extreme and mean ratio (golden section). 193 More probable, however, is the interpretation preferred by Tannery and Heath that ‘section’ means the section of solids, 194 which might correspond to no. 6 on our list. Also unclear remains the question of Eudoxus’ solution to the problem of doubling the cube. Eratosthenes’ epigram and his letter to King Ptolemy III mention ‘curved lines’ (kampúlai grammaí); Eutocius, however, who quotes both these texts, leaves Eudoxus’ solution out. As he explains, the ‘curved lines’ Eudoxus mentions in the ‘introduction’ are not found in the text of the proof and a discrete proportion is used here as if it were continuous ( Download 1.41 Mb. Do'stlaringiz bilan baham: |
Ma'lumotlar bazasi mualliflik huquqi bilan himoyalangan ©fayllar.org 2024
ma'muriyatiga murojaat qiling
ma'muriyatiga murojaat qiling