Al-Ghaza¯lı¯’s Philosophical


Download 4.03 Mb.
Pdf ko'rish
bet36/55
Sana07.11.2017
Hajmi4.03 Mb.
#19584
1   ...   32   33   34   35   36   37   38   39   ...   55

41

  In his  Book of the Forty ,  al-Ghaza¯lı¯ adds that God’s decree ( qad.a¯ 7)  



is both the same as His eternal will and the same as His providence for His 

creation, which is expressed through the order that He creates. 

42

  

  The Highest Goal  is only marginally concerned with ethics and thus does 



not delve as deeply into the nature of human actions as  Revival  does. Yet al-

Ghaza¯lı¯ also makes clear here that God creates everything in this world, in-

cluding human actions. He creates the action as well as the place (or substrate,  

mah.all ) that receives the action, which is the human. He also creates the con-

ditions for the action’s reception and whatever else contributes to it. 

43

  God re-



quires humans to “make themselves open” to the outfl ow of God’s mercy upon 

them, to the creation of benefi cial knowledge in them that will lead to praise-

worthy actions. 

44

  



 In   The Highest Goal,   al-Ghaza¯lı¯ shows the same ambivalence as in  Revival  

with regard to the necessity of the system God creates. God cannot create any-

thing whose conditions for its existence are not fulfi lled. 

45

  If anything were to be 



changed in God’s order, the order itself would become void. 

46

  If the harmful crea-



tions in the world were to be removed, then the good that they produce would be 

done away with and harm far worse than what currently exists would then come 

about. 

47

  Divine liberality (   ju



¯d ) requires the “perfect achievement of the utmost 

good whose existence is possible.” 

48

  Yet here in the  Highest Goal , as in many of 



his other writings, al-Ghaza¯lı¯ distinguishes God’s knowledge of how the optimal 

creation is achieved from God’s will to create the optimal. God’s actions are not 

random or coincidental but refl ect both his wisdom and his deliberation. 

49

  



  The Niche of Lights : The Philosophers’ God as the First 

Created Being 

 The   Niche of Lights   ( Mishka¯t al-anwa¯r ) is a work from the same period as  The 

Highest Goal  and  The Book of the Forty . It was written after the  Revival,   although 


2 4 6   a l - gh a z a

¯ l 1


¯ ’ s   ph ilosoph ic a l   t h e olo g y

we cannot say precisely when. Because it is one of al-Ghaza¯lı¯’s most mystical 

works, earlier chronologies of his output have dated the  Niche of Lights   to  the 

end of his career. It was assumed that during his life, al-Ghaza¯lı¯ developed a 

progressively stronger inclination toward Sufi sm, with his most mystical works 

being his last. 

50

  Such a supposition, however, is unwarranted, and the  Niche of 



Lights  could have been composed at any time after 490/1097. We do know that 

it was composed after  The Highest Goal . 

51

  

 The   Niche of Lights  is a very rich text in terms of its cosmology, and I will 



not attempt to give full justice to its complexity. Rather, I will focus on a passage 

at the very end of the book, known as the Veil Section. Soon after the  Niche of 



Light  fi rst appeared in print in 1322/1904–5, this section, which is the last of 

three in that book, inspired suffi cient controversy among Western interpret-

ers to the point that they disputed its authenticity. 

52

  This skeptical position, 



however, was based on an incomplete view of al-Ghaza¯lı¯’s theology, and today 

there can be no doubt that all parts of the text of the  Niche of Lights , as we have 

it today, are authentically al-Ghaza¯lı¯’s. 

53

  



 The Veil Section at the end of the  Niche of Lights  is not immediately related 

to the two earlier parts of the book and can be viewed on its own, to a certain de-

gree. Averroes regarded it as the clearest evidence that al-Ghaza¯lı¯’s cosmology 

continues the tradition of the Aristotelian  fala¯sifa . 

54

  The passage is a commen-



tary on the noncanonical  h.adı¯th : “God has seventy veils of light and darkness; 

were He to lift them, the august glories of His face would burn up everybody 

whose eyesight perceives Him.” 

55

   Al-Ghaza¯lı¯ aims to explain the veils of light 



and darkness that prevent people from grasping who or what God is. He clas-

sifi es various religious groups according to the kind of veil that prevents them 

from understanding the true nature of God. In the fi rst division, he discusses 

those who are veiled by pure darkness ( mujarrad al-z.ulma ), and in the second, 

those who are veiled “by light along with darkness” ( bi-nu

¯r maqru¯n bi-z.ulma ). 

Both groups are further subdivided. They contain a range of people, from plain 

unbelievers who hold nature ( t.ab ¶)  rather than God to be the cause of the world, 

to heterodox Muslims who believe that God has a bodily form, to Mu ¶tazilites. 

 In terms of cosmology, it is most interesting what al-Ghaza¯lı¯ says about the 

third division, those veiled by pure lights ( mah.d. al-anwa¯r ). 

56

  These are people 



who have gained some insight into God’s being. They are again divided into 

three subgroups that represent different levels of insight into the divine. As 

noted by Hermann Landolt, this division closely follows the narrative of Abra-

ham’s discovery of and ascent to monotheism, as told in Sura 6, verses 75–79 

of the Qur’an. 

57

   Al-Ghaza¯lı¯ introduces this story in an earlier passage from 



the  Niche of Light . 

58

  According to the commentary literature on the Qur’an, the 



young Abraham grew up in a cave’s darkness in order to avoid the persecution 

of the Mesopotamian king Nimrod. 

59

  There, he starts searching for his Lord. 



When he leaves the cave at night, he fi rst sees a star going up in the east and 

concludes that this is his Lord. Once the star goes down in the west, however, 

he dismisses that notion. He next sees the moon rising in the east and assumes 

that this is his Lord. Again, when the moon sets in the west, he rejects this 

notion. The same happens with the sun: he sees it going up in the morning 


 

c os m olo g y   in   wor k s   w r i t t e n   a f t er  



THE

 

REVIVAL

  2 4 7


and thinks it his Lord until it sets in the evening. Finally, Abraham concludes 

that none of these celestial bodies is his Lord. Rather, the maker of them, the 

Creator of the heavens and the earth, is his real Lord, and only He should be 

worshiped. 

 Abraham’s discovery of true monotheism by studying the heavens held 

great signifi cance for al-Ghaza¯lı¯, and he refers to it in other works. 

60

  In the 



third division of the Veil Section, he compares the three subgroups of scholars 

who are veiled by pure light to the three false levels of insight that Abraham 

had gained during his youth. Only a fourth group of people who are not veiled, 

“those who have arrived” ( al-wa¯s.ilu¯n ), represents the level of those who truly 

understand who the Lord is. Only this group has gained a proper understand-

ing of God ( tawh.ı¯d ). 

 Following the pattern of Abraham’s discovery, al-Ghaza¯lı¯ connects the false 

insight gained by each of the three groups with the celestial being that they 

assume is “the Lord.” These celestial beings come from the ten spheres and 

their governing intellects as they appear in al-Fa¯ra¯bı¯’s model of cosmology. The 

fourfold model in this section (three false groups plus one correct) combines 

philosophical cosmology with doxography or even heresiography. 

 Al-Ghaza¯lı¯ says the lowest of these three subgroups are people who hold 

the opinion that the mover of the highest visible heaven, which is the next-to-

outermost sphere, the sphere of the fi xed stars, is the creator of the world and 

the “Lord”: 

 The  fi rst among them is a group ( t.a¯ 7ifa ) that knows the meanings 

of the [divine] attributes properly  (tah.qı¯qan ) and realizes that the 

nouns “speech,” “will,” “power,” and “knowledge,” and others cannot 

apply to God’s attributes the way that they apply to humans. In their 

teachings ( ta rı¯f   ) about God these people avoid using these attributes. 

When they teach about Him they draw upon the relationship [of 

God] to the created things just like Moses, peace be upon him, taught 

about God in his answer to Pharaoh’s question: “What is the ‘Lord of 

the Worlds’ ”? (Q 26:23). These people say the Lord, who is the Holy 

One and who is exalted over the meanings of these attributes, is the 

mover of the heavens and the one who governs ( dabbara )  them. 

61

  



 Compared to the groups mentioned earlier in the veil section—those veiled by 

some kind of darkness—this group has developed a proper understanding of 

the divine attributes and their transcendence. They understand that the Lord 

is exalted over all anthropomorphic attributes. When they use words such as 

“speech,” “will,” “power,” and “knowledge” to describe the Lord; they intend 

their meaning to transcend the ordinary sense of these words. This passage 

refers to the polemics between Ash ¶arites and Mu ¶tazilites. The latter are the 

highest group from the earlier part of those veiled by light and darkness and 

have just been discussed. Ash ¶arites criticized Mu ¶tazilites for assuming that 

the human understanding of justice, for instance, is the same as God’s under-

standing. The group described in this passage has gained more insight than 

the Mu ¶tazilites and understands that all of God’s attributes are transcendent. 



2 4 8   a l - gh a z a

¯ l 1


¯ ’ s   ph ilosoph ic a l   t h e olo g y

When they are pressed by their opponents to explain who is the “Lord of the 

worlds,” they answer what Moses told Pharaoh, namely, that God is “the Lord 

of the heavens and the earth and all in between” (Qur’an 26:24) and that He is 

“your Lord and the Lord of your forefathers” (26:26). Pharao asked him about 

the essence ( ma¯hiyya ) of the divine, al-Ghaza¯lı¯ remarks earlier in the  Niche of 



Lights , and Moses responded about the acts of God. 

62

  Likewise this group draws 



on God’s relation to the created things. Their understanding of divine tran-

scendence leads them to the insight that the Lord is the one who moves and 

governs the heavens ( muharrik al-samawa¯t wa-mudabbiruhu ). 

 The shortcomings of this position are still quite signifi cant, and they are 

highlighted in the discussion of the next higher group: 

 The second group leaves these people behind insofar as it became 

clear to them that there is multiplicity ( kathra ) in the heavens, and 

that the mover of each single heaven is a different being that is called 

an angel, of whom there are many. Their (scil. the angels) relation to 

the divine lights ( al-anwa¯r al-ila¯hiyya ) is the relation of the stars. 

63

  

 The  fi rst group incorrectly believes the Lord to be the mover of the next-to-outer 



sphere, whom they view as the governor ( mudabbir ) of the visible heavens and 

the cause for the existence of the heavenly bodies. They assume the existence 

of a single mover of one large heavenly sphere and are unaware of the exist-

ence of multiple spheres, each having a mover who may also be called an angel 

malak ). 

 The last sentence in this passage about the angels’ relation ( nisba )  to  the 

divine lights has proved diffi cult to understand. The sentence is incomplete 

or at least elliptical, as it analogizes the angels’ relationship to the divine lights 

with the stars’ relationship to . . . nothing. A clue to understanding it can be 

found in al-Ghaza¯lı¯’s  Decisive Criterion   ( Fays.al al-tafriqa ). There, al-Ghaza¯lı¯ re-

ports that some Sufi s interpret the Qur’anic narrative of Abraham seeing the 

star, the moon, and the sun and identifying them as his Lord in terms of “lu-

minous, angelic substances” (   jawa¯hir nu

¯ra¯niyya malakiyya ), to which the words 

“star, moon, and sun” refer. These substances are purely intellectual and not 

perceived through the senses, and they have advancing degrees of perfection 

daraja¯t mutafa¯wita f ı¯ l-kama¯l ). The passage ends with the sentence: “The rela-

tion ( nisba ) of the amount of differences between one another is like the relation 

between the star, the moon, and the sun.” 

64

  Here in the Veil Section, the relation 



of the angels to the divine lights—most probably a reference to God—is the 

same as the star’s relation to the real Lord in Abraham’s vision. To complete the 

elliptical sentence, the words “to the true Lord,” or something similar, should 

be added to its end. Although this sentence remains enigmatic, it is clear that 

the fi rst level of insight into the divine is likened to the one Abraham reached 

when in Q 6:76, he erroneously discovers that the star ( al-kawkab ) is his Lord. 

 In the Veil Section, al-Ghaza¯lı¯ adopts a distinctly philosophical perspective 

and looks at the world with eyes trained in philosophical cosmology. His fi rst 

subgroup is defi ned by its failure to understand the “multiplicity in the heav-

ens.” We will see that the next group can be roughly identifi ed with Aristotle and 



 

c os m olo g y   in   wor k s   w r i t t e n   a f t er  



THE

 

REVIVAL

  2 4 9


his followers. It seems that when he envisions the fi rst group, al-Ghaza¯lı¯ uses 

the widespread typology of his time for understanding the history of philoso-

phy, visualizing that group as typifying a pre-Aristotelian stage of philosophy. 

The supposed failure to recognize multiplicity in the heavens indicates a group 

that did not believe in the existence of more than one heavenly sphere. The 

Jewish Aristotelian philosopher Maimonides (d. 601/1204), who wrote three 

generations after al-Ghaza¯lı¯, ascribes this view to a group of ancient natural 

philosophers. In his  Guide of the Perplexed   ( Dala¯lat al-h.a¯ 7irı¯n ), he comments on 

the cosmology of the earliest generations of philosophers who lived at the times 

of the Sabians, the pagan polytheists with whom Abraham struggled: 

 The utmost attained by the speculation of those who philosophized 

in those [early] times consisted in imagining that God was the spirit 

of the sphere ( ru

¯h. al-falak ) and that the sphere and the stars are the 

body of which the deity, may He be exalted, is its spirit. 

65

  

 Maimonides refers his readers to Ibn Ba¯jja’s (d. 533/1139) commentary on Ar-



istotle’s  Physics . The reference is not entirely clear, since Ibn Ba¯jja neither dis-

cusses the cosmology of the early philosophers nor mentions the Sabians. Ibn 

Ba¯jja, who wrote one generation after al-Ghaza¯lı¯ in the Muslim West, com-

ments on Aristotle’s refutation of the teachings of earlier Greek philosophers, 

most notably Parmenides and Melissos. These early philosophers taught that 

all that exists is the manifestation of a single unchanging and unlimited princi-

ple. There are no real processes in the world, Parmenides taught; rather, what 

really exists—meaning, what exists on the level of intellectual forms, unaf-

fected by sense perception—is unchanging. Refl ecting on Aristotle’s writings 

on these teachings in Book 1 of his  Physics , Ibn Ba¯jja says that Parmenides 

and Melissos saw no differences between different existing beings and treated 

them as if they were all of one kind. This was before the time when Aristotle 

alerted philosophers to the fundamental difference between beings. 

66

  But de-



spite Aristotle’s attempts to defi ne physics as a science that analyzes processes, 

the teachings of these earliest philosophers prevailed. The  mutakallimu



¯n ,  Ibn 

Ba¯jja complains, hold basically the same teachings. He implicitly refers to the 

occasionalism of the Ash ¶arites. The  mutakallimu

¯n  reject the existence of natu-

ral dispositions ( al-t.iba¯ ¶) , Ibn Ba¯jja says, and claim that everything consists of 

atoms. The views of the  mutakallimu

¯n  are not based on any research, writes Ibn 

Ba¯jja; rather, they have developed these views unsystematically in their internal 

polemics. 

67

  



 Ibn  Ba¯jja’s remarks on pre-Aristotelian science are part of a larger tradition 

of  Physics  commentary in Arabic. 

68

  In Avicenna’s discussion of the  Physics   in  his 



 Healing,  he also connects the teachings of Parmenides and Melissos with the 

theory of atomism. 

69

  According to Avicenna’s analysis, pre-Aristotelian theories 



of physics and the opinions of the classical Ash ¶arite  mutakallimu

¯n  are errone-

ous for the same reason: they disregard the substantial differences between 

beings that underlie Aristotelian physics, such as the difference between a sub-

stance and an accident or the difference between composed beings in the sub-

lunar sphere and uncomposed beings in the heavenly spheres. The atomism 


2 5 0   a l - gh a z a

¯ l 1


¯ ’ s   ph ilosoph ic a l   t h e olo g y

of the Ash ¶arite  mutakallimu



¯n —and by implication, their occasionalism—is 

just one expression of this disregard for the Aristotelian distinctions between 

beings. For an Ash ¶arite occasionalist, all beings consist of indistinguishable 

smaller parts that are equally close to God’s creative activity. 

 The  fi rst group’s failure to understand that there is multiplicity ( kathra )  in 

the heavens may have a more subtle meaning than just the acknowledgment 

of numerous spheres. Al-Ghaza¯lı¯ may have adopted the Aristotelians’ position 

regarding early theories of cosmology. Pre-Aristotelian cosmology was marred 

both by the failure to understand that there are numerous spheres as well as 

by a lack of distinction between different types of beings. The cosmological 

beliefs of this fi rst group seem to identify them with this early group of phi-

losophers. Additionally, al-Ghaza¯lı¯ may be writing on a naive understanding of 

occasionalism. Such an occasionalism would simply assume that all things are 

composed of atoms and accidents and would deny, for instance, the existence 

of self-subsisting intellects. The failure to understand the “multiplicity in the 

heavens”—a deliberately unspecifi c description—may be meant to refer both 

to an early philosophical approach by pre-Aristotelian thinkers and to a naive 

occasionalist understanding of the universe. 

 The fact that the fi rst subgroup in this division has a proper understanding of 

God’s transcendence implies its identifi cation with Ash ¶arism. According to their 

own view, the Ash ¶arites were the only group of Muslim theologians to under-

stand the transcendence of the divine attributes. In his works, al-Ghaza¯lı¯ tirelessly 

stressed the transcendence of the divine attributes. In the Arabic doxographic 

tradition, early philosophers also held the view that God is transcendent. The 

Arabic doxography of pseudo-Ammonius, which was available from the middle 

of the third/ninth century, reports that pre-Socratic philosophers such as Thales 

and Pythagoras taught the transcendence of the divine attributes, attributes that 

neither the human intellect nor the soul is able to comprehend. 

70

  A generation 



after al-Ghaza¯lı¯, al-Shahrasta¯nı¯ repeats these reports in his  Book of Religions and 

Creeds . 

71

  Since this fi rst group is characterized as understanding the transcend-



ence of God’s attributes while misunderstanding the composition of the heavens 

and perhaps also of the world, al-Ghaza¯lı¯ may have had been referring either to 

the Ash ¶arites or to the pre-Aristotelian philosophers or perhaps even to both. 

 Compared to this fi rst subgroup, the second subgroup of those veiled by pure 

light is described as possessing superior insight and believing that the next higher 

celestial being—the mover of the highest sphere—is their Lord. I have already 

quoted the passage detailing the group’s understanding that there are many heav-

enly spheres and that each sphere has its own mover. The passage continues: 

 Then it became evident to them that these heavens are inside another 

celestial sphere that moves all the others through its motion once 

during [every] day and night. They said the Lord is the mover of that 

celestial body which is furthest away and which envelops all celestial 

spheres since multiplicity is denied to Him. 

72

  



 In comparison with the fi rst group, this group has an adequate understanding 

of astronomy and the celestial spheres. Here al-Ghaza¯lı¯ describes the introduc-



 

c os m olo g y   in   wor k s   w r i t t e n   a f t er  



THE

 

REVIVAL

  2 5 1


tion of the  primum mobile , the outermost starless sphere, as fi rst theorized by 

Ptolemy. 

73

  This group’s Lord is the mover of the  primum mobile . Given that 



there are no physical movements above this sphere, this Lord himself is the 


Download 4.03 Mb.

Do'stlaringiz bilan baham:
1   ...   32   33   34   35   36   37   38   39   ...   55




Ma'lumotlar bazasi mualliflik huquqi bilan himoyalangan ©fayllar.org 2024
ma'muriyatiga murojaat qiling